E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
The publication of “Over Ruled: The Human Toll of Too Much
Law” by Justice Gorsuch and Janie Nitze (no link, deliberately), coupled with
my getting to another book in the genre “too much law” as I read down my
accumulated shelf of unread books provoked me to think about the genre.
The form of the genre is this: (1) an account of some horror
stories in which law or the absence of law inflicted real human harm according
to the author, who typically offers an unnuanced and somewhat distorted account
of the facts and the law (or non-law) at issue followed by (2) a diagnosis,
often sounding in political economy, of why these horror stories occurred, and
concluding with (3) some prescriptions about what to do about the problem. My general
sense, and something that might be worked up by someone else into an
interesting survey article, is that there’s typically a disconnect between the
diagnosis and the prescription, which ordinarily occurs because the author isn’t
willing to rethink the hard-wired features of the US Constitution that give
rise to the political economy that causes the problem. (That’s drastically
simplified, and a full account would say something about American Political Development and about how sometimes modest
prescriptions can dynamically change the surrounding political economy—a bit
more on this later.)
As I’ve suggested there are conservative and liberal exemplars
of the genre. Strikingly, though, it seems to me that authors on both sides
converge on a political economy story in which the self-interest of political
actors and special interest groups determine policy, along the lines of Mancur
Olsen’s “concentrated benefits/distributed costs” model. One might think, then,
that the prescriptions would try to work out governance structures that would
be less vulnerable to the Olsen-like problems.
And sometimes you do find such prescriptions. Conservatives,
for example, argue for a sharply reduced scope of public power so that special
interests can’t get any concentrated benefits from government. Liberals, in
contrast, follow James Madison’s model of an expanded republic with substantial
power in the center, which increases the costs of organizing to obtain
concentrated benefits (though when you get them, the benefits are larger than
would occur in a less centralized government). Notably, it often takes a fair
amount of pulling and hauling to get these results out of the existing
hard-wired US constitutional system.
So, the prescriptions get a bit removed from the diagnosis. Sometimes
the prescription is something along the lines of “Shape up and fly right.” That
is, the people should become more politically active and in particular should vigorously
oppose candidates supported by special interests. Here the difficulty is that
the prescription doesn’t address the “distributed costs” part of Olsen’s
argument (or, if you want, doesn’t address the paradox of voting in large
polities, to put it telegraphically).
Another favored prescription is judicial empowerment (or
engagement in the Institute of Justice’s preferred language). The judges we
have, selected in the way we select them, should (and will, if only they read
this book?) interpret the Constitution and existing statutes in an anti-Olsen
way. Here the Institute for Justice’s favorite cases, some of which Gorsuch and
Nitze apparently discuss—undertakers, hair-braiders, flower arrangers—are pretty
good exemplars, as are the stories of intrepid plaintiffs’ side lawyers
successfully taking on corporate power. Except for the facts that (a) the IJ’s cases
involve rather small problems in an overall scheme of “too much/too little law”
and (b) those cases, and even more the liberal-side cases, are probably
better addressed through centralized initiatives like the Obama and Biden
administrations’ campaign against “professional” licensing laws and non-compete
clauses and aggressive centralized regulation.
A further problem with the judicial empowerment prescription
is that it lacks a political economy. Or, maybe better, it doesn’t have an
account of how judges selected in an Olsen-like political process will actually
administer the preferred remedies. We now know enough about state-level
judicial selection to see the problem—and it’s a defect in the legal and
political science literature that we don’t have a decent account of the political
economy of federal judicial selection today (the historical literature, and in
particular Jed Shugerman’s book, does offer a political economy account of state-level
and, a bit, national-level judicial selection from the founding to roughly the
end of the New Deal/Great Society era).
As I’ve hinted, another route would be to locate Olsen-like governance
structures in the hard-wired Constitution—and to attempt to eliminate those
structures by radically restructuring the Constitution—abolish federalism or
radically decentralize, regionalize, get rid of the Senate, mandate proportional
representation, whatever. I’m not interested in the merits of these
prescriptions but rather am interested in their structure.
I think you can find a tiny bit of this kind of thinking
among strong conservative libertarians, typically (I think) not embedded in today’s
legal community. My guess is that the reason is that today’s conservatives
think, perhaps correctly, that they have a lock on the federal judiciary and so
judicial empowerment is good enough even if they understand it’s a contingent
fact rather than the result of something structural about the political system.
One possible result of this year’s presidential election might be to place this
contingent fact under pressure (the other result would of course solidify it).
There’s a bit more of structural thinking on the progressive
side, perhaps (the obverse of my observation about conservatives and the
federal courts) faut de mieux. Campaign finance reform is probably the most
prominent example, though it seems to me that discussions of such proposals by liberals
don’t take seriously enough the Olsen-like problems associated with getting
campaign finance reforms actually enacted and implemented.
Advocacy for non-reformist reforms by today’s LPE scholars
is probably a better example. In my understanding (which I stress might not be
that of proponents of the non-reformist reforms on the table), non-reformist
reforms are within the range of policy innovations that might plausibly emerge
from our current governance structures but that, when implemented, might have a
dynamic effect of destabilizing those structures (particularly when taken
together with seemingly unrelated non-reformist reforms in entirely separate
domains).
Policy prescriptions aren’t my bag so I can’t say much about
non-reformist reforms except this. First, they do connect the diagnosis and the
prescription in the right way. Second, to my taste (which is historically contingent
and influenced by living through the CLS experience), the LPE project is a bit
too hostile to whacko policy proposals that have no chance whatever of adoption
in the reasonably short run but push the normative commitments of progressives
and liberals to the limit and thereby might (I think CLS did) dramatically
expand the range within which non-reformist reforms might operate. (I have a
sociological account of the CLS-LPE relation that’s akin to but somewhat
different from Sam Moyn’s.) I should note as well that there's a parallel involving whacko proposals on the conservative side.