Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Back to the sources: How to interpret the Constitution, according to Cass Sunstein (Part II)
|
Tuesday, December 19, 2023
Back to the sources: How to interpret the Constitution, according to Cass Sunstein (Part II)
Guest Blogger
Roberto Gargarella Some critical notes In the first part of this paper,
I described some of the central features of Cass Sunstein's new book, How to
interpret the Constitution. In that initial part, I referred to the
different interpretative theories presented by Sunstein in his book, and also to
the method he proposed for selecting a theory of constitutional interpretation
from among them. The method in question was the Rawlsian "reflective
equilibrium", built on the basis of certain "fixed points" or
paradigmatic judicial cases (say, in the case of American law, judicial
decisions such as Brown or Griswold), and also with the help of
other theoretical "fixed points" (in his proposal, deliberative
democracy and the "anti-caste principle"). Having completed that
descriptive introduction, I will now present the second part of my analysis,
which will be of a more evaluative and critical nature. I will first make two
brief introductory remarks, and then move to a more substantive examination of Sunstein’s
new work. On the other hand, and now in
favor of this particular new book, I would say that Sunstein’s “return to the
sources” is interesting, because it allows us to re-encounter the "old
Sunstein", who had made excellent contributions to law. That “old Sunstein”
was the one who produced exciting papers like "Beyond the Republican
Revival" or highly illuminating books like After the Rights Revolution or
The Partial Constitution. Sunstein was, at that time, a progressive
democrat who favored the egalitarian philosophy of John Rawls and defended
Ronald Dworkin’s legal philosophy -theories that he would later set aside,
perhaps too quickly. Sunstein's early works were supported by a broad-based and
attractive conception, whose parts were mutually reinforcing. That conception
included a republican reading of legal history (based on a controversial but
exciting reading of the works of James Madison and Thomas Jefferson), and a
deliberative conception of democracy (like the one advanced by Jurgen Habermas or
Jon Elster). On a more substantive level, I
will first mention that the book does a good job regarding one of its central
proposals, namely introducing the problem of constitutional interpretation and critically
examining the main existing interpretative theories. To be clear, Sunstein
offers a succinct rather than meticulous examination of those theories, but
this is because his work is mainly directed at people unfamiliar with the
subject. In any case, the book is didactic, and his approach to the subject may
be considered to be well-balanced and well-grounded (although some critics said
that the task Sunstein undertakes, precisely on this point, fails crucially).[5] In contrast to the above, I think
that Sunstein’s theoretical approach, in this book, is controversial and
difficult to sustain. Once again, my general impression is that, unfortunately,
Sunstein throws his theory into the public forum too soon. In that way, he
leaves it at the mercy of severe and largely avoidable criticisms. More
specifically, I believe that the main analytical tools that he proposes - the
"reflective equilibrium," the "fixed points," the
supporting theories (deliberative democracy, the anti-caste principle) - are
hastily and sloppily presented, which makes his whole theoretical apparatus
fragile. Let me begin by referring to the
"supporting theories" (this is to say, to the last two "fixed
points" presented by the author), namely deliberative democracy and the
anti-caste principle. As I understand it, Sunstein's defense of both issues is
in need of a more careful and robust support. Given the central role that such
ideas play in sustaining his position, one would have expected a less
superficial and more detailed treatment of those issues. Sunstein admits this
deficiency in the last pages of his book. He makes it clear, then, that he is
"perfectly aware" that these two ideas introduced at the end of his
work (although very present in his initial studies) would require much more
development. By way of apology, he mentions that his purpose was to "point
in the direction of such ideas," and to "the centrality" that
such conceptions have regarding "the particular approach to constitutional
law" favored in his book (ibid., 164). We can take these clarifications
for good, of course, but the truth is that recognizing or being fully aware of
the problems that affect a proposition does not strengthen it, nor make it more
rigorous: the deficit remains, and it is a serious deficit. Just to illustrate my point: one
of the main ways in which Sunstein tries to support the relevance of resorting
to those ideas (deliberative democracy and the anti-caste principle), is by
showing the link that would exist between both conceptions and the roots of American
law. However, the arguments that he presents in this respect are weak and not
persuasive: Sunstein pretends that we take, as generally accepted, too
controversial considerations. Think, for example, about the proposition that
"the founding fathers" adhered to a deliberative understanding of
democracy (which would be contradicted by the more common assumption that they assumed
a "pluralist" or polyarchic conception of democracy). Alternatively,
think about his claim regarding the presence of a strong and egalitarian
version of republicanism, during the founding years (which would be another
highly controversial claim, if we consider that the majority of those founding
fathers were, just to begin, slave-owners).[6] In
sum, such empirical claims are highly controversial. The fact is that
Sunstein's interpretive approach ends up being based on very controversial
assumptions, which should not be presented as if they were not. Much less, if
what he intends to do is present such principles as "fixed points",
widely shared by all members of the community (I will come back to this last
issue below). Let me add a further note on the
character of those two ideas or principles (deliberative democracy, the
anti-caste principle) as "fixed points" of law. I begin by recalling
the following: when presenting his vision on the "fixed points" of
law, Sunstein mentions certain judicial decisions (such as Brown or Griswold)
that all or almost all of us tend to recognize as benchmarks of American law.
Fine. Now, it is something very different to say, then, that a theory like
deliberative democracy, or a principle like the anti-caste principle, are also
"fixed points" of law. This seems strange. I claim that the move is strange,
first, in relation to the object of that reflection. The question is: is
it appropriate to examine abstract principles (such as “deliberative democracy”
or “the anti-caste principle”), through the same analytical tools (the
"reflective equilibrium," the "fixed points") that we employ
to evaluate the status of well-known and well-established legal decisions? It
does not seem so. We might for instance say that, after long decades, we have
socially converged in the endorsement of certain particular judicial decisions
(Brown). However, it does not make sense to say the same about a
theory of deliberative democracy or a particular reading of equality. Regarding
those issues, it is difficult to recognize a collective "point of
convergence". This, among other things, because we reflect less, collectively,
about them (these are issues that are not part of our public conversation); but
also, because the levels of disagreement we show on such matters seem much
higher. The problem is, as we shall see, that Sunstein presents his approach,
rigorously, in one form, but also in the opposite form, or open to multiple
exceptions, in such a way that his vision ends up being diffuse and elusive. [7] Sunstein's approach in this
respect is also strange at a different level: the one related to the subject
of this reasoning. The question is: are we talking about agreements that
all or the vast majority of the members of our legal community seem to have
about the law (i.e., we all think that any reading about the law must be able
to recognize the value of a decision like Brown); or are we
referring, instead, to individual legal criteria, about which we are personally
persuaded (i.e., because we are individually convinced about the value of the
theory of deliberative democracy)? Between the Theory of Justice and
the “chain novel” This last point helps us to
address another question, more directly related to the method of
"reflective equilibrium" -I mean, “reflective equilibrium” according
to the version sponsored at the time by John Rawls. In his reference to the matter,
Rawls did not appeal to -say- very intense personal preferences or convictions
derived from one's philosophy or ideology. He referred to convictions
fundamentally shared by all members of our community. For that reason, in his
references to the subject, Rawls alluded to examples such as those of religious
intolerance and racial discrimination. What I mean to say is that Rawls
referred to issues on which the vast majority of society seemed to agree
fundamentally. In his words (which were written in the first-person plural): Sunstein is well aware of this
view (chapter 4). However, in the ecumenical and conciliatory approach that he
develops in the book, Sunstein suggests a different view on the matter. He presents the matter as if each person
selected his or her “fixed points” and then engaged in a process of “reflective
equilibrium”. He examines these issues as if there were no conclusive reasons
to say that such a conception, such a theory, or such a "fixed point"
were the correct one (for all). For that motive, Sunstein may claim -after he
presented his “own fixed points”: "these propositions are correct...These
are my fixed points; they are part of my reflective equilibrium"
(Sunstein, 2023, p. 161). For him, “each chooser -each one of us- must make a
judgment about what those fixed points are, about exactly how fixed they are,
and about whether one or another approach would endanger them” (ibid., p. 129).
Now: this is not how we usually understand the idea of "reflective
equilibrium," much less is this the way Rawls thought about the question. I
insist: we are not dealing with issues fundamentally related to our personal
preferences or theoretical convictions (where everyone has his views and where
everyone's views, in principle, are equally plausible or reasonable). More
specifically: when Rawls says that “we are confident that religious intolerance
and racial discrimination are unjust” he is not thinking about those problems
as a matter of “choice”. On the contrary, he is thinking of (something like)
the collective recognition or acknowledgement of a problem that is common to
all -a problem that is evident to all. The problem at stake is of such an
entity that everyone can confidently point to it as a serious problem. In
other words, it is not a debatable issue, about which, as Sunstein suggests, we
have to "anticipate and offer convincing responses to
counterarguments" (Sunstein 2023, p. 128). In fact, if these were highly
debatable questions (if we had to make such intellectual efforts in order to
persuade others about the importance of such problems), we would not be talking
of "fixed points" in Rawls's terms. I have said something about
Sunstein's approach to "fixed points" and its relation to Rawls's
theory of justice, and now I want to say something about that theoretical
approach and Ronald Dworkin’s theory of interpretation. I am thinking, in
particular, of the interpretive theory presented by Dworkin in terms of the
"chain novel." As we know, Dworkin’s “chain-novel-approach” to legal
interpretation suggest that the task before the interpreter of the law is
similar to that of the one who participates in the writing of a "chain
novel" (Dworkin, 1986). To summarize Dworkin’s view in a nutshell: to do
his or her job correctly, the participant in the "chain novel" must
"look back," read what has already been written by previous
participants, make sense of what has been written by all, and then determine
what the "best possible continuation" of that collective novel is- a
continuation that is capable of "accommodating" in the best way all
that has already been written. In law, the (interpretative) task would (should)
demand a similar intellectual exercise: the judge or interpreter looks back and
seeks to make sense of all the written law to then determine what is the best
possible continuation of that law, in the specific case under examination (a
decision that “fits” with the past legal history). His decision, in that
specific case, must "fit" well, in Dworkin's terms, with what has
been decided so far by the legal community, read in "its best light."
Or, to put it another way, that decision must fit with what Sunstein calls
"fixed points" (it must make sense of Brown, Griswold, the
rejection of Lochner, etc.). The point is, so far,
that in spite of the differences that separate the two authors (and perhaps
despite Sunstein's own intentions), there are important points of coincidence between
Dworkin’ and Sunstein’s work in the area. Among other coincidences, i) both
authors are interested in the constructive interpretation of social practices; ii)
both relate constitutional interpretation to an analysis of the community’s
legal history; iii) both pay special attention to paradigmatic judicial
decisions; and iv) both seek to reconstruct that legal history through a
normatively charged approach. Now, I was interested in drawing
attention to the (non-expected) coincidences that appear between the two
authors but, above all, in highlighting the crucial differences that exist between
their approaches. First of all, while Sunstein seeks to derive, from his
proposed "fixed points," the choice of an "interpretative
theory," Dworkin seeks to derive, simply, the resolution of a concrete
case. For example, faced with a case in which an affirmative action law is
challenged, Dworkin might say that it is appropriate to uphold - rather than
invalidate - that law if it can be demonstrated that this particular decision –
say, the defense of a certain affirmative action measure - makes it possible to
give an appropriate account of Brown and a whole saga of
cases were racial equality, the dignity of the person, and so on, were
sustained. My impression is that the enterprise undertaken by Dworkin
(inferring the resolution of a case, from a well-established legal tradition)
is much more natural and reasonable than that proposed by Sunstein (deducing
the choice of an interpretive theory, from certain "fixed points"). The task proposed by Dworkin is
more "natural" and reasonable, because it relates well to practices
that most members of the legal community engage in, in one way or another. In
fact -I submit- we usually think about the decision of a particular case,
taking into account (in a more or less sophisticated way) legal decisions that
have been made in the past, in similar cases or circumstances. We may or may
not adhere to this approach (take it as our preferred approach) but it refers
us to a task that in no way seems strange to us. Sunstein's proposal, on the
other hand, appears as less "natural", if not directly
counter-intuitive. For him, “the search for reflective equilibrium” plays a
central role in constitutional law. “In fact” -he claims- “it is the only game
in town”: “we cannot pull a theory of the sky, insist that it must be right,
and declare victory” (Sunstein 2023, p. 11). But here, again, Sunstein seems to
be mixing things up. We can affirm with him that, somehow, some kind of
"reflexive equilibrium" plays "a central role in constitutional
law". But that does not lead us to conclude, by any means, that this
exercise of "reflective equilibrium" is the one we set in motion
"in deciding how to interpret the Constitution" (or, even more
strongly, when “choosing” the best interpretative theory). Those are two
completely different claims. In fact, he still needs to convince us that we
tend to look to past paradigmatic decisions in order to “choose” an interpretative
theory. In other words, this does not seem to be the way in which we usually come
to “defend” a certain theory of constitutional interpretation. The question is: Do
we first “choose” or define, say, certain paradigmatic judicial decisions, in
order to then “choose” an interpretative theory? Or is the exercise at stake
rather the reverse? Most probably, the interpretative theory that Sunstein claims
to find "at the end of the road" was already present from the very
beginning. So, Sunstein’s proposal in this regard seems to be not only unusual
but also unreasonable if not simply wrong. In fact, Dworkin could rightly
point out that the theory now in question (the one that Sunstein seeks to
derive from history) pre-existed the proposed exercise. We assume a theory of
constitutional interpretation that first tells us to pay attention to certain
"fixed points"; then helps us to "choose" or recognize some
"fixed points" from our long legal history (say, take up Brown,
discard Lochner); and then induces us to organize them in a certain way,
or to derive from them other conclusions. In sum: the theory is the one that marks
all the way from the beginning, not the one we choose or find at the end of the
road. Through this brief review, I wanted
to celebrate the publication of Cass Sunstein's How to Interpret the
Constitution. This is a book that - on a personal level - reconciles
me with an author that I have followed and admired during decades. Beyond the
differences noted, I applaud what appears to be a "return to the
sources" on the part of Sunstein. And I do so with the hope of
encountering new works by the author, reflecting on constitutional law from a
perspective committed to democracy, equality and social justice. Roberto Gargarella is Professor of Constitutional Law at the Universidad de Buenos Aires. You can reach him by e-mail at roberto.gargarella@gmail.com. BIBLIOGRAFIA Breyer,
S. (2011), Making Our Democracy Work, New York: Vintage. Dworkin,
R. (1977), Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Dworkin,
R. (1986), Law’s Empire, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Elster,
J. (1986) “The Market and the Forum”, en J. Elster & A. Hylland (eds.), Foundations
of social choice theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1986, 103
132. Ely,
J. (1980), Democracy and Distrust, Cambridge, Harvard University Press. Habermas,
J. (1988), Between Facts and Norms, Cambridge, The MIT Press. Holloway, C. (2024), “The Great Constitutional Divide”,
The National Review. Magazine, https://www.nationalreview.com/magazine/2024/01/the-great-constitutional-divide/ Rawls,
J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Sunstein,
C. (1984) "Naked Preferences and the Constitution," 84 Columbia
Law Review 1689. Sunstein,
C. (1988) “Beyond the Republican Revival”, 97 Yale L. J. 1539. Sunstein,
C. (1990), After the Rights Revolution, Cambridge: Harvard University
Press. Sunstein,
C. (1993), The Partial Constitution, Cambridge, Harvard University
Press. Sunstein,
C. (1994), “The Anticaste Principle,” Mich. L. Rev. 92, 2410. Sunstein,
C. (1999) One case at a time. Judicial minimalism on the Supreme Court,
Cambridge, Harvard U.P. Sunstein,
C. (2015), “There is Nothing that Interpretation Just Is,” Constitutional
Commentary 30. Sunstein,
C. (2023), How to interpret the Constitution, Princeton: Princeton
University Press. Sunstein, C. & Vermeule, A. “Interpretation and Institutions,” 101 Mich. L. Rev. 885
(2003). Thaler,
R. & Sunstein, C. (2009), Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health,
Wealth, and Happiness, London: Penguin Books. Thayer,
J. (1893), “The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional
Law, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 7, No. 3 (Oct. 25), pp. 129-156. Roberto
Gargarella. Doctor in Law (University of Buenos Aires); Jurisprudence Doctor
(University of Chicago). CONICET (Argentina)/ Univ. Pompeu Fabra (Spain) [5] In his
review of Sunstein’s book, for example, Carson Holloway maintains that
Sunstein’s analysis “fails in its main purposes”, and also that “his denials
are unconvincing”, particularly in what regards the merits of originalist
interpretative theories (Holloway 2024). [6] However,
and partially denying his immediately previous statements, Sunstein recognizes
that the “republicanism” that he links to the “founding era” was “patently
violated until the Civil War Amendments” Sunstein 2023, 163. [7] As
usual, Sunstein is not blind to this problem, but he instead deals with it
without much rigor. He emphatically claims, for instance: “It is important to
say that fixed point about constitutional law are not…fixed points about
morality and justice” (Sunstein 2023, p. 13). But, in the very same phrase he
clarifies that what he actually meant to say is that they “are not simply,
fixed points about morality and justice” (ibid., italics added). To add more
complexity (and ambiguity) to the problem, Sunstein admits that “our fixed
points operate at multiple levels of generality” (ibid.), and also that “they
are not only about specific cases”, because they may be “abstract”. In this
way, everything seems to be possible.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |