E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Essentially Contested Histories: On Recent Efforts to Cabin the Meanings of Slavery and Disestablishment
Andrew Koppelman
Some of the Constitution’s provisions decree that certain specific historical evils must not happen again. Such provisions generate a unique interpretive problem. The object of interpretation is not a word or a phrase, but a repudiated cluster of practices. Any construction of such provisions must offer a description of what was wrong with the original evil, so that the interpreter can decide whether the challenged action repeats that wrong.
The description will inevitably be shaped by the values of the interpreter. Every historical episode is susceptible to multiple interpretations, depending on which aspects the interpreter deems salient. One danger, which happened in the past and is happening again, is that an interpreter who is untroubled by some aspects of the historical evil may improperly narrow its scope by deeming those aspects outside the prohibition.
I illustrate this by focusing on two constitutional provisions, the Thirteenth Amendment’s prohibition of slavery and the First Amendment’s prohibition of establishments of religion. Each has been subjected to narrowing constructions, which focus on uncontroversial aspects of the historical wrong and then assert without further argument that they exhaust the provision’s coverage.
The most recent instance of this maneuver is Justice Gorsuch’s reformulation of Establishment Clause law, cited with approval in his opinion for the Court in Kennedy v. Bremerton, which would allow previously impermissible public endorsements of specific religious beliefs. His interpretive strategy is the same one that the Court used to restrict the scope of the Thirteenth Amendment in the Civil Rights Cases, Plessy v. Ferguson, and Hodges v. United States.