Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Softening Blunt Instruments: Michelman’s Constitutional Essentials on the Horizontal Effect of Constitutional Rights
|
Sunday, October 15, 2023
Softening Blunt Instruments: Michelman’s Constitutional Essentials on the Horizontal Effect of Constitutional Rights
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Frank Michelman, Constitutional Essentials: On the Constitutional Theory of Political Liberalism (Oxford University Press, 2022) Richard
Mailey “Constitutional
law … is an instrument too blunt to be fit for the work.” To begin with a quick clarification: the
above quote is not Michelman’s own view, but a constructive challenge that he
poses for those who are critical of state-centric conceptions of constitutional
rights law. The challenge, put simply, is how to make constitutional law an appropriate “regulatory engine” for
addressing the threat posed by concentrations of power in non-governmental or
private hands (CE, at 187). What makes this so challenging is that there is a sense
(at least in some minds) that allowing courts to address privately inflicted
harm through the application of constitutional rights law “amounts to bypass of
democratic legislative competence, popular knowledge and wisdom, and political
freedom” (ibid). As Michelman
continues, the apparent problem is that constitutionalizing so-called
“horizontal” relations means “hand[ing] over to a judiciary not chosen either
for regulatory acumen or sensitivity to public opinion the translation into
concrete regulatory policy of the abstractly formulated clauses of guarantee
native … to liberal constitutions” (ibid). One of the great strengths of Constitutional Essentials is that
Michelman doesn’t attempt to definitively resolve the problems he seeks to unfurl,
including the problem of horizontal effect described above. In this regard, I’m
reminded of something that Robert Post wrote a decade or so ago: This passage perfectly encapsulates the
Michelmanian method as it’s applied to the problem of horizontal effect in Chapter
13 of Constitutional Essentials. To
be sure, there is a hint at a solution on the chapter’s penultimate page — a
mild preference for consideration of constitutional demands by “the traditional
array of private law tribunals” (CE, at 190) — but it’s tentative and general enough
to stand as an invitation for further reflection, rather than a conclusive
claim that “this is the Rawlsian way.” That said, it’s worth noting that this
solution, tentative as it may be, resonates strongly with the approach that the
Supreme Court of Canada has taken to the problem of horizontality. In 1986,
just four years after the passage of Canada’s Charter of Rights and Freedoms, the Supreme Court held that while
the Charter doesn’t apply directly to
courts or the common law — at least in the context of purely private litigation
— it has residual relevance when it comes to the common law’s application and
development (RWDSU v Dolphin Delivery).
Nearly a decade later, in Hill v Church
of Scientology, the Court clarified that this residual relevance obliges
courts to engage in principled balancing, weighing Charter values against “the principles which underlie the common
law,” and using those values as “guidelines for any modification to the common
law which the court feels is necessary” (Hill,
para 97). This approach, the Court said, was designed to ensure that
“[f]ar-reaching changes to the common law [are] left to the legislature,” with
courts sticking to their “traditional” role of incremental development as
opposed to full blown revision or policy-making (Hill, para 96). In one sense, this seems like an
appropriate way of meeting to a pair of potentially contradictory needs. On the
one hand, section 52 of the Canadian Constitution
Act, 1982 makes the Charter (and
indeed, the entire Constitution) applicable to “all law,” to the point of
rendering inconsistent laws “of no force or effect.” On the other hand, though,
there was a significant risk that bringing the “abstractly formulated clauses”
(to borrow Michelman’s phrasing) of the Charter
to bear directly on the private common law would open it up to ad hoc revision
by ill-equipped actors (judges), subjecting private persons to an unstable
regulatory environment and disturbing the constitutional separation of powers.
In effect, the Supreme Court’s middle ground response was to make the Charter applicable to the common law,
but in a way that allows courts to do work that they already did: the work of
incrementally developing the law to ensure its consistency with contemporary
social norms and expectations (as reflected in the Charter). Yes, the Charter
legally applies to “all law,” the Court effectively said; but no, not in
exactly the same way, or with exactly the same remedial results. Here’s the catch, though. Consider the
strange inconsistency that emerges when you single out the background rules of
the common law for special constitutional treatment. If a private party relies
on a statutory provision in private litigation, the Charter applies in full and has the potential to trigger a standard
constitutional rights analysis directed at that provision. By contrast, if that
same party relies on a common law rule, the other party is deprived of their
ability to request a full Charter
analysis, or the remedy of judicial invalidation that potentially follows it.
Instead, the aggrieved party is now in the weaker position of claiming that the
common law rule is inconsistent with a Charter
“value,” that this inconsistency is not offset sufficiently by the principles
that underlie the rule, and that modification of the common law within
reasonable limits is appropriate. Add to that the fact that the aggrieved party
now bears the burden of proving all of this — rather than having the state bear
the burden of justifying the law — and you suddenly have a quite significant
and seemingly arbitrary weakening of the claimant’s position that depends on
whether the impugned rule is a product of legislative or judicial hands. As the
late Peter Hogg put it: “It seems odd that the applicability of the Charter should turn on the question
whether the applicable law is a rule of the common law or a rule of statute
law” (Hogg, at 277). Of course, Michelman’s comments on the
horizontal effect problem don’t suggest support for the Supreme Court of
Canada’s very specific approach, but they do arguably gesture in this direction,
at least insofar as they imply that private law tribunals should cultivate
their own distinctive approach to constitutional review, and insofar as this
inevitably requires the type of arbitrary line drawing that we’ve seen in
Canada. If this is true, though, one may legitimately respond with a brisk
burst of realism: maybe such an approach is simply the best that we can do,
given the tension that I laid out above between the need for constitutional
efficacy and private law stability. I’m fatalistic enough that I’m almost
swayed by this response, but let’s nonetheless ask, for the sake of argument:
is this really the best that we can
do, on Michelman’s own terms? To begin answering this question: another
great thing about Constitutional
Essentials is that it is so thoroughly teeming with ideas, and it’s
accordingly unsurprising that earlier chapters offer promising (although ultimately
untapped) insights for dealing with the horizontal effect problem. For example,
in a few short paragraphs on judicial supremacy, Michelman writes that: What’s so helpful about this passage is
that it directly addresses the fear that is embedded in Michelman’s framing of
the horizontal effect problem. Recall that this fear was motivated, in part, by
a sense that horizontalizing constitutional rights means “bypassing” the
political branches, and allowing courts to take on the job of “translating”
constitutional demands into “concrete regulatory policy.” The paragraph quoted
above, however, points to some of the steps that can be taken to ensure that
this “translation” work is meaningfully shared, and that democratically
accountable actors remain centre stage, despite the judicial application of full constitutional scrutiny to all law. To follow this thread, consider two of
the “remedial devices” mentioned above: remands to the political branches, and
tolerance for interpretive disagreement. In Canada, the first of these is reflected
(for example) by the judicial practice of issuing suspended declarations of
invalidity, which began in the Manitoba
Language Reference (1985) and continued, most notably, with the Supreme
Court’s Carter decision on medical
assistance in dying. As a response to the horizontal effect problem, such
suspended declarations of invalidity could have tremendous value, since they
mitigate the fears of legislative bypass and judicial policy-making, as well as
the connected fear of overzealous intrusions in previously settled areas of
private law doctrine. The idea here would be that a court faced with an
impugned common law rule could subject that rule to full-fledged Charter analysis, and could strike the
rule down if it failed to pass muster, with the proviso that the invalidation
wouldn’t become effective until, say, a year or two later. In this scenario,
there would be 1) no regulatory vacuum, 2) no sudden disturbance of a settled area of private law, and 3) full
legislative control over “concrete regulatory policy,” since the buck would
effectively be passed to the legislature to remedy the constitutional problem
before the invalidity kicked in. Rather than using constitutional law as a
blunt instrument, then, the suspended declaration would use it as a way to
trigger legislative review and improvement, all while redeeming the promise of
section 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982,
i.e. the promise that unconstitutional laws will not just be incrementally
improved, but will have “no force or effect.” What about the second remedial device,
then? Here, the obvious example is the Charter’s
ever-contentious notwithstanding clause, which allows Canadian legislatures to
derogate from certain constitutional rights commitments for renewable five-year
periods. While the notwithstanding clause has rightly generated a lot of
controversy of late, much of this, I suggest, is because too little has been
done to ensure that derogation is accompanied by a sufficiently
rights-sensitive public dialogue, and by meaningfully independent oversight of
government action. If Canadian legislatures took steps to require such dialogue
and oversight — as Ian Peach and I argue they should in a forthcoming article (Peach
and Mailey, 2023) — the notwithstanding clause could evolve into a legitimate
secondary means of avoiding legislative vacuums in cases where courts
invalidate private common law rules. Crucially, though, the notwithstanding
clause can also allow legislatures to temporarily register reasonable
disagreement with a judicial finding that a private law rule is
unconstitutional, and to (again temporarily) revive the rule and the balance
that it sought to strike between competing values. On its own, this will surely
smack of governmental fiat, but if it is supplemented by the focused
deliberations of a legislative committee, or a citizen’s jury, say, it might
take on a deeper hue of dialogic democratic legitimacy. The point being: the
notwithstanding clause could, under the right circumstances and with the right
additional laws in place, mitigate the juristocratic risks laid out at the
start of this post while still allowing courts to apply full constitutional
scrutiny to the rules that contour private affairs and interactions. *** To clarify: nothing that I have written
here goes against the grain of Michelman’s chapter on horizontal effect, but
rather seeks to extend it in a Michelmanian direction via insights developed
elsewhere in Constitutional Essentials.
At the same time, though, if there is one critical point worth making, it is
perhaps that more scrutiny could be applied, within the horizontality chapter,
to the assumptions that animate opposition to full horizontal effect — most
notably the assumption that constitutional law is a necessarily blunt
instrument. To be sure, if constitutionalism is cast as a blunt instrument,
Michelman’s challenge is correctly framed; but, as the examples above suggest,
blunt instruments can be productively softened, provided that one is attentive
to the risks that come along with such softening (especially in the case of the
notwithstanding clause). Richard Mailey is Director, Centre for Constitutional Studies, at the University of Alberta. You can reach him by e-mail at mailey@ualberta.ca. References Books
and Articles Hogg, Peter, “The Dolphin Delivery Case: The Application of the Charter to Private Action” (1986) 51 Saskatchewan Law Review 273 Michelman, Frank, Constitutional Essentials: On the Constitutional Theory of Political
Liberalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2022) [abbreviated as “CE”] Peach, Ian & Richard Mailey,
“Weaving Section 33 into the Charter Project: Citizen-Led Oversight as a
Potential Way Out of the Legitimacy Conundrum” (2023) 32:3 Constitutional Forum
(Forthcoming) Post, Robert, “Provocation: Frank’s Way”
(2011) 125 Harvard Law Review Forum 218 Cases Carter
v Canada (AG), [2015] 1 SCR 331 Hill
v Church of Scientology, [1995] 2 SCR 1130 Reference
re Manitoba Language Rights, [1992] 1 SCR 212 RWDSU
v Dolphin Delivery, [1986] 2 SCR 573
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |