Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts “A picture drawn from life” -- Comments on Frank Michelman’s Constitutional Essentials (“CE”)
|
Tuesday, October 10, 2023
“A picture drawn from life” -- Comments on Frank Michelman’s Constitutional Essentials (“CE”)
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization Symposium on Frank Michelman, Constitutional Essentials: On the Constitutional Theory of Political Liberalism (Oxford University Press, 2022) Oliver Gerstenberg
A crucial insight in Frank’s CE is
that constitutions may serve a justificatory or proceduralizing aim in modern
liberal democracies. Constitutions, for sure, serve a regulatory role, as Frank
says, working from an expectation of advance-design effects on political
outcomes. However, on the assumption that in morally divided societies nearly
all citizens will regard some of the coercive laws as deeply wrong, unjust and
repugnant, constitutions can provide an important framework of justification
which enables political majorities to justify their coercive enactments to
dissenters from majoritarian legislation by showing that they have acted within
the terms of a good-enough constitution. As Frank has pointed out elsewhere,
“[o]n the level of mundane political rhetoric ‘it’s constitutional, after all’
…. works … as a formidable reposte to those who demand to know why they should
be expected to accept in good spirit the compulsion of some law that they (not
crazily) have found to be outrageous and oppressive.” “Procedures,” as Frank explains in his book,
“are a resort for groups of persons who find themselves divided over policies
for their group but who even so prefer (or see no choice but) to stick together
rather than go their separate ways.” Constitutions proceduralize the
resolution of those disagreements by providing a justificational framework
which reasonably disposed citizens can mutually share. Substantive
constitutional law has as one of its chief functions to serve as a public
standard for a democratic regime’s continued deservingness of wide
acceptability in advanced democracies, so that citizens will be justified in
demanding of each other a general disposition of compliance with all
constitutionally compliant laws regardless of their own, independent judgments
of the moral and other merits of these laws. But substantive constitutional law qualifies
to fulfil this proceduralizing mission, “if and only if the procedure can be
counted fair among free and equal citizens in conditions of reasonable
pluralism,” that is, if but only if the procedure is also substantive in that
it protects all the rights, but only those rights, that would make this a
constitutional pact acceptable to all citizens considered as free and equal.
Only under this condition does the procedure have a “supportable claim on the
consent of all reasonable and rational parties affected” and can be seen “in
the last resort an upshot from the pursuit of the liberal grail of government
by consent,” expressing its “liberal character.” In this way, proceduralization expresses the
complex normative fact that all citizens must be able to see themselves and
each other not only the addressees, but also the putative joint co-authors of
the coercively imposed legal order. Only then can dissenters be expected to
accept political and legal outcomes even when those outcomes diverge from our
personal preferences, moral judgments or conceptions of justice. Yet the constitutional framework will
necessarily contain a significant number of highly abstract, open-textured
terms whose applications to concrete cases will be subject to ongoing and
persistent good-faith interpretive disagreements. The proceduralizing strategy
therefore depends on further agreement on a forum or process for trustworthy
reasonable resolutions of such disagreements about the framework's content,
which may be courts. In order for the proceduralizing strategy to work, two
conditions must be met: first, judges must be, “and appear to be, interpreting
the same constitution” and, second, it must be the case that the judges’ views
of the constitutional essentials locate the central range of the basic freedoms
in more or less the same place. But the problem—to which Frank has been
drawing our attention all-along—is that the entire strategy of
proceduralisation may fail. Legitimacy-endangering dissensus may move
all-the-way up into the proceduralizing constitutional framework itself and
extend right into core civil and political rights which form the citizens’
“constitutional-procedural pact.” The conditions of visionary pluralism might
turn against constitutional law itself as a platform of justification that can
be mutually shared by all in good faith. Then any democratic-dualist-legalist
distinction between constitutional law and ordinary law becomes impossible to
achieve. Given the pervasiveness of deep moral
dissensus, is a defense of democratic-dualist legalism possible? A familiar contemporary critique argues that
conditions of modern pluralism and moral dissensus render the dualist-democratic
idea of subjection of ordinary democratic lawmaking to the constraints of a
higher-law constitution obsolete. As the critics argue, it would be much
better—more democratic—to leave majorities to decide by themselves, liberated
from constitutional constraint. Constitutions inevitably orient us toward the
past not the future, thereby distorting our contemporary debates about the pros
and cons of policies themselves by backward-looking questions about fidelity to
some (imagined) past. Instead, we should pursue the fundamental values we care
about—from antidiscrimination to environmental justice—through the to-and-fro’
of unconstrained majoritarian politics itself. I believe that Frank is exactly right in
arguing that a liberally justification-worthy political framework-law-in-place
is normatively necessary for democratic politics to succeed in divided
societies and in claiming that this is a “picture drawn from life.” The overall message of Frank’s CE does
not come across as defeatist. Political liberalism, as Frank says elsewhere, is
a “fighting faith.” Liberal democracy, Frank argues, rests on “public
confidence shared and sustained in a liberally
justification-worthy political framework law-in-place.” And contrary to the
political-constitutionalist view that the law of lawmaking should be determined
by ordinary politics entirely, courts can exert a legitimacy-sustaining and
democracy-enhancing role. Ronald Dworkin had argued that judicial decisions should be based on
the principles that make the best sense of the Constitution’s provisions, while
keeping faith with understandings arrived at in previous cases. Sometimes an
active judicial role will be justified, and precisely in the interest of
democracy as a non-majoritarian substantive concept, grounded in the value of
political equality. Frank, too, does not abandon the project of justification
and the effort of getting the basic laws and their major interpretations morally
right. However, a center-piece of Frank’s work has been to explore
the idea of temporality and dialectical liberal reasonability which focus on
relationships between courts and the wider public—in other words, "an
institutional division of labor between the supreme court and the people.” Already back in 1999, in Brennan and
Democracy, Frank wrote that “the maximum feasible effort to get the basic laws and their major interpretations right would
have to include arrangements for exposing the empowered basic-law interpreters
to the full blast of sundry opinions and interest-articulations in society,
including on a fair basis everyone’s opinions and articulations, including your
own.” Expanding on this “full-blast” condition by introducing, in CE, a
non-court-centric, less judicially-supremacist conception of constitutional
adjudication characterized by a temporal dialectical-liberal dimension, Frank
argues that constitutional interpretation is a recursive, self-revising process
involving the constant interplay between courts, legislatures, plaintiffs, the
citizens themselves, the wider public. Under conditions of visionary pluralism
democratically responsible citizens—who mutually understand themselves as
“heirs to a broad constitutional-democratic tradition”—are “pressing sundry
views within a broad space allowed by the constitutional-democratic tradition
can compose a constant force-in-waiting for provocation
of updated adjustment of the scheme of constitutional guarantees in force
in their country, so as always to be dragging it toward its fully
justification-worthy state.” In divided societies, constitutional-interpretive
deliberation itself, as I read Frank, can do something to engender discursive civility
and mutual respect across moral disagreement, provided that each side listens
with respect to the other’s particularist inflection of
constitutional-interpretive claims and demands. This gradualist and reformist impulse in
Frank’s approach, aimed at widening the circle of reasonability, dovetails with
what Frank has described as a “democratic experimentalist model” of courts, and
with “social learning.” Toward the end of chapter 10, which is on the specific
debate on socio-economic rights and their justiciability (which I will not
pursue here), Frank describes a broader, more forward-looking,
deliberation-enhancing role of courts. The court “acts in the first instance as
instigator and non-dictatorial overseer of engagements among stakeholders very
broadly defined—governments of course included—in an ongoing process of
interpretative clarification of what a constitutionally declared right … The
court engages the parties over what sorts of steps by what classes of actors
are concretely … now in order … As the discursive benchmarking moves along and
the emerging answers gain public recognition and authorization, the court turns
up the heat on deployment of its powers of review … At later stages, the court
starts calling for substantive compliance with an emergent best-practice
consensus, in the name of the constitutional right … [but without claiming] a
door-closing last word.” The democratic-experimentalist model, then,
conceives of democracy as essentially deliberative: as a process of
mutual perspective-taking between citizens as free and equal in morally divided
societies which allows and requires co-deliberators—conflict parties, state
actors, third parties and stakeholders generally, either as proponents or
dissenters—to consider and rethink their initial commitments, internalizing
elements of their opponents’ antagonistic views thereby transforming their own.
In this way, the democratic process ties the exercise of public power back not
only to the preferences but to the judgments of citizens as political equals. Courts
can play an important deliberation-reinforcing role in instigating and
monitoring a non-hierarchical process of stakeholder deliberation in which
forms of manipulation, distortion or social domination can routinely be
addressed, openly be criticized, and remedied, often over self-correcting successive
litigation. The democratic-experimentalist model allows for—as compatible with
the principle of institutional settlement—modalities of judicial intervention
that remain provisional and open to social learning and input and ongoing
self-revision by focusing on the process of progressive clarification of the
meaning of rights that citizens, in turn, are encouraged to mobilize, and on
the process of searching for fair balance over time. Attention focuses not only
on the exceptional hard case and a singular court deciding it, but on
multilevel constitutionalism. There no longer is personification of political
community, but the idea instead is that judicial intervention may contribute to
an antagonistic consensus on the process itself of reasoned debate and
deliberation: a convergent understanding, in a morally divided society, that
this justificatory-deliberative procedure is without alternative and hence
always self-substituting.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |