Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Why Amendment "Difficulty" Matters
|
Tuesday, January 24, 2023
Why Amendment "Difficulty" Matters
Stephen Griffin
For the Balkinization 20th Anniversary Symposium My commemorative post to Balkinization is from my current project developing a theory of constitutional change for the U.S. case. This part of the project discusses why the “difficulty” of constitutional amendment under Article V matters. This topic is highly relevant to the “state of constitutional theory” because although important, it operates largely as an out of sight assumption. But if it is a hidden assumption, it is an issue that makes a difference. For example, in my article “Optimistic Originalism and the Reconstruction Amendments,” I wrote: “Originalist adherence to Article V as the sole legitimate means of constitutional change is a red thread that runs through and unifies what are otherwise quite disparate versions of the theory.” Nonoriginalists or living constitutionalists have their own take on Article V, which is that change is simply “impossible.” Historians seem to agree. In a recent issue of The New Yorker, Jill Lepore wrote, “With the failure of the E.R.A., the Constitution became effectively unamendable.” Historian Michael Vorenberg argues that prior to the Civil War, Americans did not regard Article V as offering a reasonable way to handle their urgent constitutional disputes. They saw the Constitution as appropriately static, in keeping with the argument James Madison made in The Federalist No. 49. The controversy over slavery supports this point as well. The political stresses caused by the nullification crisis in the 1830s or Dred Scott in the 1850s did not cause Americans to turn to amendments as solutions except just before the Civil War broke out. The phenomenon of amendment avoidance cuts across the standard debate over amendment difficulty. Arguments asserting the general difficulty or, even, “impossibility” of amendment are questionable given the ratification of twenty-seven amendments (or fifteen since the founding period), including some that everyone agrees are of great importance and a few that were ratified quickly. In this light, the inquiry into amendment difficulty needs to be recast. The “difficulty” of amendment that is relevant to my argument is the consequence of a conflict of values – between specifying limitations on government that are enforceable and kept up to date while also keeping the Constitution clear of quotidian political entanglements in the service of stability. Understood in this way, the contention that the Constitution is too “difficult” to formally change is not chiefly about mechanics or observing the number or frequency of amendments, but a complex historical and normative judgment about the relevance of the text to ongoing governance. Such an inquiry involves establishing a historical baseline composed of the norms and institutions of the eighteenth-century state and then comparing it with the norms and institutions needed to drive forward the far more complex national state of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. Amendment difficulty is thus a relative judgment about the adequacy of the existing text to ground the operation of the contemporary American state rather than a claim about the unchanging difficulty of jumping through the hoops established by Article V. It is more a question of the benefits and costs of deliberate amendment avoidance than amendment “difficulty.” During the long interregnum between the Twelfth Amendment and the Thirteenth, there were several disputes that illustrate the logic of amendment avoidance. As with the debate over internal improvements, in debates over the constitutionality of territorial expansion, states’ rights, and the status of slavery nineteenth-century Americans came to rely on non-amendment or “informal” means to make (or at least advocate, in the case of proposals not adopted) significant legal changes to the Constitution. Why? As perhaps the most important basis for political identity, the Constitution came to have a near-sacrosanct character. Proponents of changes in government power were therefore reluctant to concede that formally changing the Constitution was necessary. After all, advocating a change to the Constitution implied that it was defective, a position that was almost self-refuting from a political point of view. Nonetheless, advocates of using federal constitutional power in an active way sometimes controlled the government and so did change the scope of federal constitutional power – but without using amendments. This can leave us at sea if we attempt to track the evolution of constitutional power in antebellum America (and afterwards). Tracking constitutional change matters because the law matters. One must keep in mind both the original commitment to a supreme law governing politics and the later decision to, in effect, push much constitutional change, legal change, off-text. Without a reliable way to track non-amendment constitutional change, we would not know the content of the supreme law of the land. Over time, the literal text would tell us less and less. The logic of change I have described was so taken for granted by Americans that it was not until well into the Civil War that Republicans realized that only a formal constitutional amendment would guarantee the legal death of slavery. Republicans almost universally believed, for example, that the Constitution did not provide the federal government with the power to abolish slavery within an existing state. In his wonderful account historian James Oakes describes the pervasive “federal consensus” to the effect “that the Constitution put slavery in the states beyond the reach of federal power.” No specific clause of the Constitution actually stated this, of course, “yet no other constitutional precept so profoundly shaped the contours of antislavery politics in the years between the founding of the nation and the Civil War.” Slavery was grounded firmly in law and hence was not so easy to abolish. Despite this growing realization of the legal “stickiness” of slavery, Republicans still had doubts about using the Article V amendment process. Here Oakes’s account dovetails with Vorenberg’s. Reverence for the Constitution made amendment, the one option that was certain to end slavery forever, seem too difficult. Republicans gradually came to the realization that the fault lay with the Constitution itself. It may appear that Republicans were caught in a tangled net of principled distinctions of their own devising. The point I wish to press is that we would find similar fine distinctions being made with respect to any of the significant constitutional controversies in American history. These distinctions are based on principles like the federal consensus that are part of the law of the Constitution. Regardless of whether they were literally ensconced in the constitutional text or not, these principles were regarded by contemporaries as the supreme law of the land. This meant that proposing changes to those principles required an amendment to the Constitution or its legal equivalent. Whether the change ultimately happened through Article V or not, the Constitution would be changed as a result. This suggests strongly that the Thirteenth Amendment (and, of course, the Fourteenth Amendment as well) changed multiple aspects of the structure of the eighteenth-century Constitution. Not just slavery was abolished, but the “federal consensus,” the idea that there were features of state law that absolutely had to be beyond federal control. This is precisely why Democrats opposed the amendment. As Oakes rightly concludes, the Thirteenth Amendment “implied a fundamentally different view of the nature of the federal Union. For Democrats freedom depended on state rights, and slavery was one of the things states were by right free to have.” But not once the Thirteenth Amendment was ratified, of course. Provided it was supported by state building, the nature of American federalism had changed and so with it, the baseline for understanding future constitutional development. The resistance to amendment in antebellum America, even during the Civil War, shows plainly that a deep political logic lay behind the phenomenon of amendment avoidance. Furthermore, the circumstances of the Reconstruction amendments cuts against the view that Article V has served the country well as an avenue toward reasonable reform. Although no one doubts that the Reconstruction amendments made fundamental changes to the Constitution, the fact that it took the bloody struggle of the Civil War to ensure their adoption shows that public officials did not easily accept that amendments are sometimes necessary to accomplish essential political reforms. Although some scholars point to the Progressive era amendments as showing that Article V can be used to make reasonable reforms, historical research (by Lisa McGirr in terms of Prohibition) has also suggested a powerful link between some of these amendments and the consensus needed to fight World War I. Again, significant constitutional change seems to require a war, which counts against the idea that Article V is a reasonable, available outlet for reform. It is not news that an enormous amount of constitutional change happened off-text in some sense in the twentieth century. But there has been an issue of how best to characterize this change. So far, the new element added by my argument is that the foundation for this non-textual, non-amendment change was laid by repeated decisions in the antebellum era to resist amendments, what I have termed amendment avoidance. Amendment avoidance implies that at least some of the constitutional changes of the twentieth century could have been roughly at the level of the Reconstruction amendments, truly epochal changes to the constitutional order (although the promise of the amendments may have been undermined as we will discuss below). Is there a plausible way to vindicate and justify this intuition? The test my theory imposes is that the asserted change be a departure from the original constitutional baseline, conceived in historicist terms. Further, the change must be reflected in positive law and accompanied by state building, the deliberate institutionalization of the change so it can be reproduced across generations. Among the twentieth-century changes discussed by scholars, three stand out as fulfilling these conditions rather easily: (1) a new conception of the power of the presidency; (2) a new role for the national government as a whole in regulating the economy and influencing state governance; and (3) the advent after World War II of the national security state. These examples are widely discussed in the literature and have some support as permanent constitutional changes of such significance that they can be compared to major amendments. These events are widely acknowledged, at least informally, as constitutional changes and so we might wonder what the idea of a historicist baseline contributes. In response, consider the differing reactions of conservatives and liberals to these alterations to the constitutional order. As we will see, conservatives and libertarians rejected the New Deal was an unconstitutional departure from the previous baseline while remaining mostly accepting of the new laws and institutions of the national security state. Meanwhile, liberals supported the New Deal as completely consistent with the Constitution, in line with the prominent advocacy to that effect by FDR and, eventually, the Supreme Court itself. Partly in reaction to the Eisenhower presidency, liberals came to articulate a conception of the “imperial” presidency that they would later turn against. This turn made liberals skeptical of the constitutional foundations of the national security state, making the conservative and liberal positions on the foundations of the constitutional order mirror images. One of the main virtues of insisting on a historicist baseline amid these partisan reactions and changes of view is to keep our accounts straight in the sense of leaning against the undue influence of today’s concerns. This is a deep topic which I cannot explore here. For now, consider whether the conception of national power in the early republic really supported the New Deal. Although a case can still be made that FDR was right, scholars have increasingly cast doubt on the self-confident assertions of New Dealers that the Marshall Court, for example, fully supported their conception of the commerce power. There are additional problems with the historical record as far as supporting a robust account of the presidency, particularly with respect to war powers. A historicist baseline forces us to think about these matters in terms of where things stood before these changes became a matter of ideological and partisan contention. This helps to counteract the narrative of continuity that too easily dominates legal discourse and suggests that American constitutionalism has experienced massive shifts not only in ground-level interpretations of constitutional meaning but in the structure of the institutions responsible for reproducing that meaning over time. In making these admittedly general observations from thirty thousand feet, it is wise to think globally. That is, it should be borne in mind the sheer oddity of what American constitutionalists have been trying to do for decades and are still trying to do – move forward with a very old constitution from the late eighteenth century while mostly resisting chances to update the document through amendments or overhaul it. It would be useful to compare this remarkable generations-long effort with similar long-lived constitutions in other countries, but as the leading empirical study (Elkins, Ginsburg, and Melton) confirms, there is no other country which is in the same extraordinary position. The U.S. is truly an outlier, “exceptional” if you like. Constitutional change in other countries (and in the American states!) is fast and furious compared with the Article V stasis which characterizes the U.S. at the national level. This gives us few markers to even begin to grasp how difficult this task has been or what its consequences might be. It thus should not be assumed too easily that Americans have been able to adapt the Constitution successfully outside Article V. The truth may be quite different – that there have been substantial costs to amendment avoidance. This is well illustrated by the case of conservative objections to the New Deal, a reaction which in many ways is still with us. Right up to the Reagan presidency, scholars could regard Senator Barry Goldwater’s rejection of the New Deal in his book The Conscience of a Conservative as an aberration, rejected by an overwhelming bipartisan and scholarly consensus. After the “Reagan revolution,” it wasn’t so easy. Subsequent scholarship has revealed the depths of the rejection of the principles of the New Deal among American conservatives. It is certainly true that President Eisenhower won plaudits for accepting certain features of the New Deal, such as social security and unemployment insurance. But the sort of movement conservatives who came to dominate the Republican party after Reagan took office did not see Eisenhower as one of their own. It is true that the Reagan presidency often seemed to be more about rejecting President Johnson’s Great Society rather than the New Deal. But our subsequent experience has shown this to be merely the opening move. If the New Deal had broad political support, what was the basis for conservative objections? Conservatives saw themselves as following a principled (rather than pragmatic) political theory and the New Deal violated those principles on many levels. If their theory stood for limited government, the New Deal was frankly expansionist. If they emphasized personal liberty and property rights, the New Deal stood for their systemic invasion. If the conservative reaction to crises such as depressions and wars was to see government measures as temporary, then the New Deal seemed permanent. Furthermore, all of this occurred – and it could not occur otherwise – without notable reversals by the Supreme Court in longstanding precedents and without (as conservatives saw it) any open debate on matters of constitutional principle through the only legitimate process – Article V. In this respect, there is a close connection between the concerns of contemporary originalists, conservative or not, and the Republicans who rejected the New Deal in the 1940s, 1950s and after. They share the belief that constitutional amendment is the only legitimate path to making significant constitutional changes that contravene prior law. They also share a belief that Article V is an available path – that it is not “impossible” or unreasonably difficult. This is doubly significant because it explains why conservatives have resisted as illegitimate the most likely explanation for the constitutionality of the New Deal – approval by the Supreme Court. We need to proceed cautiously in making assertions that the Court is the institution responsible for adapting the Constitution to new circumstances. Perhaps some of our fellow citizens are under the impression that certain constitutional changes can be made through amendments only. To be sure, all law students learn the cases in which the Court seemed to switch course beginning in 1937. But recall that many believe that certain Court decisions have functioned as equivalent to amendments. All you need to complete the picture is that, as the Constitution reserves amendment for a specific process in which the states have the last word and as there is a clear difference between “interpreting” the Constitution and “amending” it, it is thus illegitimate for the Court or any other branch of government to perform an amending function. This skips past what many see as the “New Deal settlement” in which there was broad acceptance of the new role for government. Taking a historicist baseline seriously, however, means perceiving that the supposed settlement was not acceptable across all political lines. I hope this discussion will begin to move the needle from relatively unproductive attempts to quantify amendment difficulty to the real issue – a choice of constitutional futures. One is where we choose to continue the experiment, unique in world history, of seeing how long we can last trying to adapt the Constitution in informal ways that are nonetheless subject to challenges of legitimacy. The other path is to make formal amendment more relevant to constitutional change by making it easier for serious proposals to be considered by Congress and the people of the United States. Stephen M. Griffin is W.R. Irby Chair and Rutledge C. Clement, Jr. Professor in Constitutional Law, Tulane Law School. Email: sgriffin@tulane.edu Posted 9:30 AM by Stephen Griffin [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |