Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Should Progressives Embrace Originalism?
|
Wednesday, December 21, 2022
Should Progressives Embrace Originalism?
Andrew Coan
In a recent post on this blog, Lawrence Solum praises Justice Ketanji Brown Jackson for “understand[ing] the dangers that judicial supremacy and living constitutionalism pose to democracy and equality—given the reality that conservative justices will dominate the Supreme Court for at least a decade or two.” Solum goes on to advance a relatively narrow critique of progressives who worry that Jackson’s approach will legitimate originalism. But his post naturally invites the broader question: If progressives cannot beat originalists, should they join them? More precisely, is originalism the best way to advance a progressive constitutional vision circa 2023? The argument, which Solum himself has not made or endorsed, would go something like this. Under present circumstances, the standard progressive constitutional arguments will never persuade a majority of the Supreme Court. Originalism, by contrast, offers progressives a fighting chance on at least some issues—perhaps quite a lot, if Solum is right about “the emancipatory power of the Fourteenth Amendment.” Originalism also offers a potent tool for criticizing the “selective mix of history, tradition, and precedent” that Solum calls “conservative living constitutionalism.” But there is an obvious problem: If and when control of the Court shifts, all of the standard progressive reasons for rejecting originalism will regain their force, and the countervailing reasons for progressives to embrace originalism today will disappear. The logical implication is that progressives will be justified in abandoning originalism whenever they next constitute a majority of the Court. This is an originalism of convenience, not the "good-faith originalism" that Solum and other originalists advocate. Yet this may be too quick. In addition to his narrow critique of progressive opponents of originalism, Solum’s post offers a capsule history tracing progressive originalism from Frederick Douglass through Justice Hugo Black to Akhil Amar, Jack Balkin, and Justice Ketanji Brown Jackson. This history is contestable, but it suggests a broader argument for progressives to embrace originalism. Perhaps the tactical advantages of progressive originalism under present circumstances are not an isolated case. Perhaps they are merely one illustration of the larger truth—captured by Solum’s historical account—that progressives have as much to gain from originalism as conservatives over the long run. Originalism will obviously not generate the result progressives favor in every case. As Solum puts it, “there is a price to be paid for good-faith originalism.” But perhaps, over the long run, progressives will do better according to their own lights by embracing originalism than they would by sticking with living constitutionalism—or by cycling between the two as circumstances dictate. Again, Solum himself does not make or endorse this argument, but it is one that we are likely to hear more of in coming years. This is an argument for “good-faith originalism,” not just an originalism of convenience. But it suffers from the same essential problem. It is one thing to embrace originalism and sacrifice crucial progressive commitments like the right to abortion when conservatives control the Court and progressives have no realistic hope of doing better. But why should any progressive be willing to make that sacrifice when the composition of the Court changes? The answer must be that abandoning originalism when it pinches would somehow make it impossible to achieve the benefits of originalism when it supports progressive outcomes. This could be true, but the mechanism that would make it so is far from obvious. Indeed, U.S. constitutional history is littered with theories forged in the crucible of earlier eras and successfully discarded when they had outlived their usefulness. Liberals famously abandoned their Lochner-era commitment to judicial restraint in the 1950s and 60s and are still reaping the benefits today. Conservatives are now in the final stages of abandoning their own earlier commitment to judicial restraint and will be reaping the benefits from this shift for decades to come. In effect, the long-run historical argument proposes originalism as a truce or middle ground between conservative living constitutionalism and progressive living constitutionalism. Progressives will understandably view this proposal as favoring conservatives and regard it skeptically for that reason. But even apart from this objection, it is difficult to see how such a truce could constitute a stable equilibrium. Whatever attraction this proposal might have for progressives under present circumstances will diminish, if not disappear, when the balance of power on the Court shifts—just as the attraction of judicial restraint has diminished, if not disappeared, for contemporary conservatives. Knowing this, conservative originalists seem unlikely to trust the sincerity of progressive converts to originalism. Among other things, this is a problem of credible commitment. It is very difficult for contemporary progressives to credibly commit their successors (or future selves) to stick with originalism two or three decades down the road. This problem is compounded by the external forces that determine the composition of the Supreme Court. Even if today’s progressive judges and intellectuals embrace good-faith originalism and teach their clerks and students to do the same, future progressive policy demanders will insist on progressive results—and the appointment of justices who will reliably produce them. This is very similar to what has happened on the conservative side in recent decades. Given these dynamics, it would be quite surprising for the conservative originalists on today’s Supreme Court to reward progressive converts with more than the occasional token victory. But if they do, progressives will have cause to worry about conservatives abandoning originalism for “common-good constitutionalism” or some close cognate. Indeed, this already seems to be a live possibility. To overcome these difficulties, defenders of progressive originalism would need either to identify an argument that unites progressives and conservatives or to devise some other solution to the credible commitment problem. Solum hints at the former when he condemns “juristocracy, whether conservative or progressive” as “a profound threat to the rule of law.” As for the latter, progressives will obviously have powerful incentives to cast their arguments in originalist terms for the foreseeable future. This shift could well have the effect of legitimating originalism that some progressives are already decrying. At a minimum, progressives who embrace originalism for short-run tactical reasons might find it costly to repudiate originalism down the road. There is also the chance that progressive originalism will resonate with the public. Together, these factors might serve as catalysts for a feedback loop making originalism increasingly attractive, at least at a rhetorical level, across the ideological spectrum. On the other hand, rule-of-law arguments for originalism have been around for a long time without persuading many progressives. Nor is originalism the only plausible alternative to the “juristocracy” Solum associates with living constitutionalism. Thayerism, popular constitutionalism, and weakening or abolishing judicial review all fit this bill, and many progressives already find them appealing. The existence of these competing strategies would make it more difficult for the two sides to coordinate on originalism as a truce, even if that truce were superior to the status quo for both progressives and conservatives. This raises the possibility that the optimal strategy for progressives in the aggregate may differ from the optimal strategy for individual progressives at the current margin. There is also the age-old question of originalism’s malleability. If both sides can often, or almost always, marshal plausible originalist arguments to support their preferred outcomes, conservative originalists will seldom feel compelled to reach progressive results and vice versa. The same goes if original meaning is indeterminate, or even conceptually incoherent, on most contested questions, as Richard Fallon has recently argued. Either of these possibilities would obviously undercut the attractiveness, and the practical significance, of originalism as a truce for both sides. These may seem like pragmatic or strategic, rather than normative, objections. But the appeal of originalism as a truce depends on good-faith originalism producing better long-run results for progressives than the available alternatives, including fair-weather or tactical originalism. That is a practical question with strategic dimensions. If conservative originalists today distrust the sincerity of progressive originalism or are simply unpersuaded by most progressive originalist arguments on the merits, progressives will not gain much by converting to originalism in the short run. Meanwhile, they will have much to lose by sticking with originalism if and when control of the Court shifts in their favor (assuming that originalism is not infinitely malleable). Any persuasive case for good-faith progressive originalism will need to find a path around these difficulties. This challenge is a general one for constitutional theory, as I explained in two posts on Supreme Court reform last week. For a fuller discussion, see my new draft essay, “What is the Matter with Dobbs?”
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |