Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Comments on the LevinsonFest Voting Rights Panel
|
Tuesday, December 27, 2022
Comments on the LevinsonFest Voting Rights Panel
Guest Blogger
This post was prepared for a
roundtable on
Voting Rights,
convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022. Sanford Levinson First
I must express my continued thanks to the persons actually behind this
remarkable project, Richard Albert, Ashley Moran, and Trish Do. And my thanks
also to Jeff Tulis for moderating this particular gathering. Quite obviously,
my deepest thanks as well to the participants. As I said at the outset of the
Zoom gathering—and on other Levinsonfests as well—I very much feel described by
the old Sesame Street staple, “Which of these things (or persons) does not
belong with the other?” Throughout my career, I have been privileged (and
tolerated) in being able to flit among quite a few different fields, but I hope
that I’ve never confused myself with those who have genuinely mastered any of
the given areas that I have been allowed to invade. I am certainly interested
in the broad area of voting rights and have accepted every invitation to any
symposium that has invited me to participate and to write something relevant to
the topic. But that does not in fact add up to deep scholarly expertise of the
kind instantiated in those who honor me with their presence. So I’m especially
pleased to read (and to comment) on what they had to say and grateful, of
course, to Jack Balkin for continuing to open Balkinization to the material
produced during these “Levinsonfests.” Nick Stephanopoulos
opens his contribution by reference to my “influential 1985 article, Gerrymandering
and the Brooding Omnipresence of Proportional Representation: Why Won’t It Go
Away?” 33 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 257
(1985) published as part of a symposium (of
course) on voting rights. Pam Karlan also hones in that piece from long ago, as
does Joey Fishkin. I confess that I’ve never had the sense that it has been
“influential, though I’m quite surprised to discover that it has apparently
been cited 111 times. But perhaps that touches on how one measures “influence”
within the sometimes strange world occupied by legal academics. For whom, after
all, do we write and hope to influence? Many years ago, I got into a strange
sort of contretemps with Judge Harry Edwards of the Court of Appeals for the
D.C. Circuit, with regard to my contribution to yet another symposium, this
time at the University of Colorado, about the “audience” for legal scholarship.
See The
Audience for Constitutional Meta-Theory (Or, Why, and To Whom, Do I Write the
Things I Do?),"
63 COL. L. AW Rev. 389-407 (1992); Judge Edwards' Indictment of
'Impractical' Scholars: The Need for a Bill of Particulars, 91 MICH. L. REV.
2110-2124 (1993).
I indicated that I wrote about whatever happened to interest me and that I
frankly did not expect any judges to be interested in what I had to say. That
was not intended to express disdain; rather, it had become quite clear that
judges in general had little demonstrated interest in legal scholarship as it
was developing in the 1980s and thereafter, when traditional doctrinal analysis
was becoming subordinated to more self-consciously “theoretical” concerns. I
relied in part on an anecdote involving a visit by Justice Scalia to the
University of Texas and and his clear lack of interest in what his friend and
former colleague Doug Laycock planned to publish in the Supreme Court Review
about his opinion in the “peyote case,” Smith v. Oregon, which basically
eviscerated the Free Exercise Clause as an independent source of constitutional
rights. Edwards was clearly offended by my essay; he is not the last judge who
has castigated the general trend of academic scholarship to become, well, more
“academic” and of less, if any, interest to the bench and bar. At least in my own case, I have become
ever more impatient with the intellectual limitations of many Supreme Court
opinions, particularly in comparison with the insights provided by “real”
political theorists or philosophers. (Fortunately, this panel is not about
“originalism,” which could, among other things, generate uncharitable comments
about the capacity of Supreme Court justices to engage in anything resembling
genuine historical analysis.) In no field that I dabble in is this theoretical
gap more evident than with regard to voting rights. I increasingly believe that
the Court, certainly as a collective institution (an “it”) and even as a
disaggregated group of individual justices (the “they”) has remarkably little
that is genuinely useful to say about the deep questions that are necessarily
presented by contemplating, for example, the idea of “representative
government,” government “by the consent of the governed,” or, ultimately, what
one might mean by a “republican form of government.” But perhaps I have the
freedom to be more than a bit insouciant in my stance because I in fact am not
really part of the field of election law specialists who properly concern
themselves, among other things, with the practical state of the doctrine and
what is truly “thinkable” at least at any given time, if one is concerned
primarily—or even significantly—with what arguments are likely in fact to
appeal to those discrete individuals we call judges, including members of our
apex court. Whatever accounts for their appointment (and confirmation), it is
unlikely to be their genuine acuity in the debates that roil professional
political theorists or philosophers, not least because there is no reason to
believe that these debates were part of their formal legal education, let alone
the subject of their actual practice. Moreover, it is unlikely that anyone who
has been a vociferous critic of some basic presuppositions of the American
political system will in fact prove attractive to those actually charged with
appointing (or confirming) judges. Just recall the sad fate of Lani Guinier
when she was nominated by President Clinton to head the Office of Civil Rights
within the Department of Justice. Not only was she successfully hounded by the
Wall Street Journal and other denizens of the right; Clinton disgraced himself
by professing, in effect, to have read her scholarly articles only for the
first time and to be upset by the ideas she was developing as part of her
critique of the American electoral system. I noted in my remarks on our
Zoom gathering that I have adored Pam Karlan as a person and as a scholar since
first meeting her many years ago. She is, without a doubt, one of the most
completely knowledgeable and probing scholars within the academy, as well as
the possessor of a truly mordant sense of humor. I am elated to consider her a
friend, and I am touched by her willingness to participate in this
“Levinsonfest.” But I have also chided her for several years because of the
title of a leading casebook—The Law of Democracy—that she co-edits with
two other good friends whom I also respect greatly and, as with Pam, have
learned much from over the years, Sam Issacharoff (a former colleague at Texas)
and Rick Pildes. From my perspective, the title is profoundly misleading and,
indeed, highly ideological inasmuch as it may serve, whether intended or not,
to reinforce the faith of students in the American electoral system. One of my
books, after all, is Our Undemocratic Constitution, and, if anything, my
qualms about our Constitution have grown immensely since I wrote it in 2006. But,
of course, to decide whether the Constitution, as defined and interpreted by
the Supreme court, is “democratic” or “undemocratic” or whether the American
system of “representative democracy” is itself “democratic” or “undemocratic”
requires that one develop a theory of democracy that can be used to measure and
assess that articulated by the Supreme Court. Indeed, one quite justified
criticism of Our Undemocratic Constitution is that it was stronger on
raw assertion than on the development and then application of a robust notion
of democracy. Physician, heal thyself! So now let me return to my
1985 essay, whether or not it was of measurable influence. What it was
attempting to do was to make the point that the Supreme Court had never come
close to offering a cogent analysis of what it actually meant by “one
person/one vote” and therefore the mantra of “equality” in voting power, which,
after all, was the basis of Reynolds v. Sims being decided as an Equal
Protection case rather, say, than as a Guarantee Clause case requiring
elaboration of what one might mean by a “republican form of government.” (This
latter point becomes the focus of my later essay on A Mantra in Search of
Meaning, also published as part of a symposium, this one at the University
of North Carolina Law School celebrating the 40th anniversary of Baker
v. Carr.) I was, and remain, impressed by Jonathan Still’s essay, published
in Ethics, where I thought (and think) that he demonstrated convincingly
that the logical entailment of equal voting power was some form of proportional
representation. This would mean, among other things, that it would be both
desirable—and perhaps even constitutionally necessary—to repeal the 1842 act of
Congress, reaffirmed in 1969, requiring single-member districts to elect
members of the House of Representatives and to require states, in structuring
their own legislatures, to reject single-member districts in favor of systems
that would allow much greater variation in those actually elected than is now
the case. To my knowledge, Still’s
essay has never been cited, let alone discussed, by any federal judge; by the
same token, I am unaware of any article other than my own that has grappled
with its arguments, though as a dabbler I would not be shocked (and in fact I
would be pleased) to discover that I am wrong. The reason for judicial
ignorance, though, is, I am confident, not that his arguments are easily
dismissable. Rather, it is almost literally inconceivable that any court would
take them truly seriously and order the kinds of radical change in our
political system that they would require. Indeed, even if one is convinced that
they are correct as abstract constitutional theory, that still leaves open the
question as to whether courts should order such changes in the face of likely
legislative resistance and, perhaps, opposition from the Executive branch as
well. So why bother? The Supreme Court has gone
out of its way, as everyone agrees, to make absolutely clear that the
Constitution, correctly read, does not require any form of proportional
representation and, according to its most recent decisions, any kind of
demonstrable “fairness” in the construction of legislative districts. Gerrymandering,
the Court has declared, is non-justiciable, Justice Kagan vociferously
disagrees on this latter point, but not at all with regard to the apparent
sanctity of non-proportional representation. But, of course, the judiciary’s
withdrawal from the area does not mean that our system is “democratic” (or even
necessarily “republican”) or that it is not in fact strangling us and
contributing ever more to the widespread American malaise about our future as a
constitutional order. I am intrigued by the fact
that Nick reads my essay as a critique of proportional representation, because
that was certainly not my intention (for what that’s worth). What I meant to be
doing was something quite simple: To point out that single-member districts
(and other aspects of our system) that generate what has often been called the
“two-party duopoly’) has consequences quite different from those produced especially
in parliamentary systems whose members are elected through some form of
proportional representation. Creation of a “government” may require intense
negotiation among members of various parties, often at cross-purposes with one
another, over the terms of creating a coalition. What this also means is that
any existing government might be quite fragile, subject to the decision of a
quite small, but nonetheless necessary, party to withdraw from the coalition. See,
e.g., Israel, which is about to have yet another probably inconclusive election
because the existing “unity” government was brought down by such a defection. I
did not mean to be praising our system inasmuch as it was (ostensibly) more
“stable” than that, say, of Italy or Israel. I meant only to point out that
there is deep tension between a desire to produce a legislature in which a
maximum number of the population can feel genuinely “represented” by people who
“look like them” or share their perhaps idiosyncratic political views, on the one
hand, and a desire instead to produce a relatively stable government,
attributable at least in part to the lack of potentially troublesome
minority blocs who cannot survive a single-member district first-past-the-post
process. The practical question,
perhaps, is the extent to which law students, who aspire, after all, to being
practicing lawyers and who therefore must take courts and judges with special
seriousness, should be taught only the “law” as enunciated by the courts.
Is it legitimate to suggest that they should also spend their time reading,
say, the works of political scientists, political theorists, and philosophers,
not because judges would necessarily be receptive to such citations, but,
rather, because students should be aware of these works in order to be
“informed citizens,” including critics of limitations in judicial perspectives?
Were I ever to agree to teach a course on “election law,” I do not believe that
I could in good faith simply ignore the great number of what I consider
intellectually defective judicial decisions in favor of assigning only the
works of Still and many others who have written about the meaning of
“democratic” or “republican” government. I often say that in my sunset years I
identify far more with my original discipline of political science than as a
lawyer. But my main home is within the legal academy, and I earn the inflated
salary that I do because I remain a legal academic and not a full-time member
of a political science department. As a relative outsider, I become free to
offer sometimes idiosyncratic perspectives, and I would like to think they’ve
been useful, at least on occasion, to those working far more within the field
of voting rights than I do. But I am certainly aware of the differences in our
respective situations. Both Nick and Pam note that
I concluded the UCLA essay with a “coda” suggesting what to me was the obvious
illegality of the winner-take-all feature of the electoral college under both
relevant legislation as well as the Equal Protection Clause. I continue to
think that is the case, and I’m actually a plaintiff in a series of suits that
Larry Lessig has organized challenging this aspect of the electoral college
(though I’d prefer its elimination entirely). So far, no court has bought the
argument, which I regard as simple and straightforward, depending only on
taking seriously the injunction in Reynolds to require “fair and
effective representation” in any multi-member legislative body. But Pam has made
the point, which I take is altogether accurate, that many lawyers concerned, as
I profess to be, with the actual consequences of an otherwise abstract theory,
might be hesitant to endorse elimination of winner-take-all unless one could be
confident that the replacement would be better, where “betterness” would almost
necessarily have political overtones. Thus Pam suggests that few Democrats in
the modern United States would be happy with replacing winner-take-all with
assignment of electoral votes by reference to congressional districts. Joe
Biden carried both Pennsylvania and Wisconsin, albeit by relatively small
majorities. Had the vote been disaggregated by congressional district, Donald
Trump would have won majorities of the electoral votes in both states because
of Republican skill in gerrymandering, which has given them a far greater
number of representatives than one might believe is justified by looking at the
overall divisions among the parties within the state as a whole. (This is a
major focus of Nick’s scholarship and his lawyerly advocacy.). The point is
that assignment of votes by congressional district would not guarantee that the
popular vote winner would in fact prevail. I still wish that someone had
challenged the electoral college on the grounds I suggested as a part of
“blowing it up.” But that may be irresponsible on my part; it is possible that
the judicially imposed cure might have in fact made the disease even worse. Joey Fishkin offers a tour of several of
my pieces. I suspect he may be the only person who has read all of them,
including one of my personal favorites, “Who Counts?” “Sez Who?” 58 ST LOUIS
L. J. 937. He correctly identifies the overall topic as “the deep problem of who ought to count as
a constituent in a representative democracy in the first place.” The fact that
we are, as a society, far more inclusive than was the case in 1787 or even
1870, does not in the least mean that the question remains only of “academic”
concern. He notes that at the time the essay was written, “the
redistricting-focused version of that debate was at the time headed for a
Supreme Court confrontation in Evenwel v. Abbott, a case that held it
was indeed constitutional for Texas to continue the near-universal American
practice of counting all residents, not just citizens or voters, for
redistricting purposes.” True enough, but the late Justice Ginsburg’s opinion
for the Court was remarkably wooden in its reasoning, even as Justice Alito, in
a concurrence, produced the equivalent of a good undergraduate essay spotting
the “deep problem” within the case but did not write what might be considered
an extended discussion or suggested solution. It is not difficult, given the
current state of American politics, to imagine that a future
Republican-dominated legislature will simply try to strip, say, Houston,
Philadelphia, or Milwaukee of the representatives it might otherwise be
entitled to by saying that a “republican form of government” requires only that
full citizens be “represented,” with aliens, even if long-term legal residents,
not being counted as part of the relevant denominator. After all, they are not
allowed to vote—the subject of yet another obscure essay of mine published as
part of a symposium, "Suffrage
and Community: Who Should Vote?" 41 U. FLA L. REV. 545-562 (1989). It
argued that political liberals, i.e., those committed to strong theories of
individuals’ right to have some say in decisions that affect their lives, could
not easily explain why the franchise is limited only to citizens, a limitation
resting far more on a civic-republican than a liberal conception of the polity.
If we are satisfied—and why should we be?—that only citizens should be allowed
to vote, then why should we necessarily oppose those latter day
(pseudo-)communitarians who wish to deny aliens membership in the collectivity
whose total number determines the number of representatives any given locality
will get? Again, though, one
might simply respond that this question, whatever its “academic” interest, is
of no interest go would-be or practicing lawyers because there is no possibility
whatsoever that the current judiciary will (or perhaps even should) declare
that it is unconstitutional to deny non-citizens the right to vote or even,
perhaps (probably?) to deny them a right to count as part of the basis for
representation. Real-life lawyers have enough to worry about, with regard to
challenges to our constitutional order and to what elements of “democracy” it
might contain, without having to take on challenges posed by “unrealistic”
hypotheticals. For me the most
interesting sentences in Joey’s thoughtful tour through my writings are the
last three: “Over time, many of the rest of us
have found ourselves moving toward some of Sandy’s once-outlandish positions. To
be clear, however, I am not in any way endorsing the crazy idea of holding a
constitutional convention. Yet.” (emphasis added). As anyone who
knows me is aware, I persist in my support for a new constitutional convention,
given my ever-increasing dismay at various features of the U.S. Constitution. Ironically,
in terms of this particular discussion, one might get rid of what I regard as
one of our system’s worst features, single-member congressional districts, by
simple legislation repealing the 1842 congressional requirement. But, just as
“everyone knows” that the Supreme Court is not about to require proportional
representation, so does “everyone” know that there are no conceivable
circumstances where a sufficient number of members of the House of
Representatives would ever vote for a statute or a constitutional amendment that
would fundamentally change their own political realities. And, of course, the
United States Constitution, unlike many state constitutions, has no possibility
of a national initiative and referendum that might do an end run around a
sclerotic Congress. (I realize that Pam, like most of my friends, is not a fan
of the idea of exporting California’s version of direct democracy to the
country at large.) So it turns out that the only practical way of
affecting this change is through a constitutional convention. QED. Should I
make it to my 90th birthday (and 50 years of being a UT faculty
member), then perhaps there will be another such occasion to engage in
collective discussion of various things that interest me, whether or not I’m
truly expert in them. I will be interested to see if Joey’s “yet” portends a
future change of mind! Professor
Torres-Spelliscy (the only member of the panel whom I had not known previously)
could not participate on the Zoom gathering, but I’m delighted that she was
able to offer her written presentation. It touches on a crucial problem of the
modern “law of democracy,” the role that money should play in elections, as
well as a somewhat exotic issue that I had not previously focused on, so-called
“ghost candidacies” of last-minute entrants to political races whose basic
function is to confuse voters by similarities of names to other candidates or,
perhaps, the sharing of what is thought to be a desirable ethnicity. Both of
these help to explain, she suggests why Florida, a state basically equally
divided in terms of voter registration of Democrats and Republicans,
nonetheless has a state legislature handily controlled by Republicans. So perhaps it is
relevant to mention one final obscure essay, Regulating Campaign Activity: The
New Road to Contradiction? 83 MICH. L. REV. 939-953 (1985), not least
because my own views are now considerably more complex (or perhaps simply
confused) than they once were. That essay was part of the University of
Michigan Law Review’s issue devoted to book reviews, and I was reviewing
Elizabeth Brenner Drew’s Politics
and Money: The New Road to Corruption (1983). At that time, I was a card-carrying member of the
American Civil Liberties Union (which remains true today), and I adopted its
then general position that money was indeed speech and that almost all
regulation of campaign finance, save perhaps for some disclosure requirements,
was presumptively unconstitutional. I presented a number of what I regarded as
clever academic points that heavy regulation of individual donations, for
example, would end up giving excessive powers to celebrities with name
recognition or, if pop stars, the ability to encourage thousands of supporters
to give small contributions. It might also give disproportionate practical
power to individuals with lots of free time on their hands rather than people
who had to work and who, therefore, could contribute money but not time. Over
time, however, I have modified my views. It simply seems willful ignorance to
deny the pernicious role that money—and the necessity to raise money—plays in
our political system. And the ability to finance “ghost candidates” is an
especially grim example of the advantages that money—and freedom from
disclosure as to where one’s support is actually coming from—can offer. Here, again, the Supreme Court is hopeless as a source of
genuine wisdom, insofar as it has firmly adopted Justice Kennedy’s obtuse view
that “corruption” lies only what is really direct bribery, an exchange of money
in return for one’s vote, as against the ability of the heavily monied to
assure that their ideological champions will in effect be able to drown out
potential opponents simply by having so many more resources to purchase
advertising and the like. However one wishes to describe it, is modern campaign
financing really part of “the law of democracy,” as against the process by
which democracy is being destroyed in the United States? (Consider in this
context that newly elected members of the United States House and Senate are regularly
informed that they must spend up to four or five hours per day making phone
calls or otherwise engaging in fundraising for the next campaign. As a matter
of fact, there now appears to be only a permanent campaign, with the
actual responsibilities for governing often taking second place to
protecting one’s own flank or otherwise proving oneself to be a loyal member of
the party team.) So perhaps I was too harsh almost 40 years ago in my relative
dismissal of her concerns about “corruption.” Do I have a “solution”? The
answer is surely no; the problems presented by campaign finance, including
genuine First Amendment considerations that I continue to believe exist, make
it exquisitely difficult. But this is not a license to ignore them or to say,
altogether correctly, that the current Supreme Court will disallow any serious
efforts at amelioration. As I mentioned on the Zoom call, I am a big fan of the work
of the senior Fishkin, Joey’s father Jim, who has devoted much of his
professional life to creating decision-making structures that do not rely on
traditional election or appointment. Instead, returning to the wisdom of
ancient Athens, Jim advocates the use, at least on occasion, of what he calls
“deliberative polls” (I would prefer the term “deliberative assemblies”)
composed of a randomly selected body of delegates. In my own course on
comparative constitutional design, I have assigned David Van Reybrouck’s Against
Elections: The Case for Democracy, which spells out the argument for
randomness in at least some aspects of government. One thing that can
unequivocally be said about random selection is that it eliminates the need for
money, save for the willingness of the polity to pay those selected for their
time spent in trying to determine what is in the public interest. I am especially
grateful for Alex Keyssar’s contribution and not only because he, too, is an
old friend from whom I have learned much, a giant on whose shoulders I am happy
to stand. He notes that he is the one non-lawyer in this group. For me,
increasingly, this is a feature, rather than a bug, for some of the reasons
I’ve earlier set out. Lawyers, for good reason, tend to become imprisoned in
the frameworks offered by the Supreme Court. The worst, none of whom is
represented today, manifest the “Stockholm syndrome” and begin arguing that the
Supreme Court’s perspective just is the correct one and that challenges
to it are illegitimate (and not only likely to be pragmatic failures). Alex is
free from such disciplinary cages. He has thus written the leading academic
history of the right to vote in the United States and, more recently, a
completely dispiriting explanation of why we still have the electoral college,
in spite of the fact that, among other things, every poll taken since 1944 has
revealed a majority that wishes to eliminate it. (The quick and dirty answer
lies in the power of white supremacist Southerners in 1969, led by Strom
Thurmond and the later Watergate-hero Sam Ervin, to filibuster a proposed
constitutional amendment that had gotten the requisite two-thirds approval in
the House and would almost certainly have received the same in the Senate had
it in fact been able to come up for a vote. But not enough supporters were
sufficiently intense to vote to overcome the filibuster.) But for me the crux
of Alex’s presentation comes in his question about “Whiggery.” Do “we” indeed
believe that darkness precedes genuine dawn (and even brilliant sunlight) and
that the “arc of history” does indeed bend toward achieving greater justice,
however hard it might be to realize that at any given time (like our own)? What
would it mean to believe that darkness begets only further darkness, until we
collapse into black holes? Like other
participants, Alex has been kind enough to read some things I have written in
the past, especially, in his case, Our Undemocratic Constitution. The
subtitle of that book is “Where the Constitution Goes Wrong (and How We the
People Can Correct It”). One might well regard that as ultimately optimistic,
offering first a perhaps dispiriting diagnosis followed by the good news that
there may be a cure—a new constitutional convention that would presumably be
willing and able to correct the problems identified in the diagnosis. So Alex
asks “whether deep within this hard-headed critic
[i.e., myself] there might lurk a Whiggish sense that things will inevitably
get better—the ‘error bred in our bones’ as Americans, particularly among those
of us who grew up in the aftermath of World War II.” This accompanies his
wondering, later in the essay, “Have
the events of the last decade battered us so badly, or shifted the terrain so
ominously, as to seriously erode the stance of Sisyphean critic?” Even Sisyphus perhaps was ever
optimistic that this time he’d get to the top with his rock, that the
past was not in fact completely predictive of the future. These are wonderful, if ominous, questions. From my perspective
Alex remains a kid; after all, he is only 75, and I am now 81. But he’s
certainly correct that many of us who did grow up in the aftermath of World War
II could not really avoid what he calls a certain Whiggishness. After all, that
was inscribed in my own life, a kid from a small town in western North
Carolina, from distinctly modest circumstances, who ends up in effect winning
the lottery, thanks, among other things, to scholarships from such institutions
as Duke University, Woodrow Wilson Foundation, the Danforth Foundation, and the
Russell Sage Foundation that allowed me to attend wonderful universities. There
is also the fact that the 1960s, in particular, saw an explosion of American
higher education; this meant that almost literally when I was in graduate
school there were no real discussions about job prospects. Jobs would be
available! As it happens, I’d like to think that the lesson learned was not that
anyone could prosper if just one worked hard. I do not think that is the case. But
I no doubt did internalize a significant degree of optimism about what would
happen to me in particular. Things would work out. In addition, I firmly
believe that no one can understand the politics of the 1960s, at least among
those along the broadly defined left, without realizing how truly optimistic
they were. Change was possible. It might not come easily. And some
people, like Schwerner, Chaney, and Goodman, died along the way. But the Civil
Rights Movement did prevail, in many important ways. And, for better and
worse, Lyndon Johnson was deterred from running from re-election because
of his disastrous policies in Vietnam. Today’s mood, I think it is safe to say, is
much more dour. Even if I remain (cautiously) optimistic about my own personal
future (save for inevitable intimations of mortality), that certainly does not
lead to any complacency about the circumstances likely to face my grandchildren
and, beyond that, of course, other members of both local and then the world
political community. I often quote Brecht, “He who laughs
has not yet heard the bad news.” Or consider Edgar’s statement in King Lear:
“The worst is not/ So long as we can
say ‘This is the worst.’” Ironically or not, at least some of
my friends who reject my call for a new constitutional convention do so by
arguing that I overestimate greatly the importance of formal constitutional
institutions or texts. To call for constitutional reform, after all, is to
suggest that it might make a difference if we switched to parliamentarianism,
or to multi-member districts with proportional representation, or replaced the
current U.S. Senate with one that might be legitimate under 21st
century notions of democracy or…. But what if, as at least some political
scientists suggest, who emphasize the dominant importance of political culture
or underlying economic realities, “reform” is a delusional hope? It may be much
too late to rectify our dilemma. Some of the Jewish prophets did suggest that
repentance would avert the catastrophes they foretold. They were the (relative)
optimists. Others said it was too late and God too angry. (One might well
reread Lincoln’s Second Inaugural from this perspective.) Exile and catastrophe
were inevitable, and the best that one might hope for is a “saving remnant” at
some far point in the future. I have often said that I view myself
as a would-be Paul Revere who is in fact a Cassandra. That is, my hope is rouse
an audience to believe that some threat is upon us—“The British are coming”—but
there is accompanying good news: We can do something about it if we meet at
Lexington and Concord. Cassandra, on the other hand, was doomed to be able to
foretell an ominous future, but no one would listen to her. Paul Revere was
“influential.” Cassandra was not. Perhaps that is the dilemma facing more and
more academics, whether they are in the legal academy or not. Sanford Levinson holds the W. St. John Garwood and W. St. John Garwood, Jr.
Centennial Chair in Law at the University of Texas Law School. He is also a
Professor in UT’s Department of Government and a Visiting Professor of Law at
Harvard Law School. You can contact him at slevinson@law.utexas.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |