Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Constructing Basic Liberties: A Meta Review
|
Tuesday, October 25, 2022
Constructing Basic Liberties: A Meta Review
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on James E. Fleming, Constructing Basic Liberties: A Defense of Substantive Due Process (University of Chicago Press, 2022). Sanford Levinson In his New York Review of Books essay “Deconstructing Dobbs,” Harvard Law School professor Laurence Tribe offers persuasive criticisms of Justice Alito’s opinion for the Court in that case and its renunciation of Roe, Casey, and other cases that viewed reproductive rights as part of the basic liberties protected by the United States Constitution through the Due Process Clause. Although James Fleming’s Constructing Basic Liberties was written prior to Dobbs, it is obvious that he shares Tribe’s animosity toward the decision, based as it is on a thoroughly desiccated notion of how one identifies basic liberties. That is, the majority of the Court is now committed to a notion of “traditionalism,” also trafficking under the title “originalism,” that require a litigant to demonstrate that the particular conduct in question was in fact embraced by the relevant American public sometime around 1787 or, with regard to Fourteenth Amendment arguments, 1868. One could write an entire essay on the Court’s notion of the relevant public when it ostensibly tries to ascertain what has come to be called “original public meaning.” Does that include, for example, women and many other marginalized groups who, to put it mildly, were not viewed as members of what Stanley Fish would later teach us to identify as “interpretive communities” whose views were treated as authoritative within their domains, including, of course, the domain of constitutional law? For Samuel Alito, it is simply utterly irrelevant that prior abortion law was constructed exclusively by males. They are literally the only people whose opinions genuinely count in his version of the law. What Fleming does is to present a supple and sophisticated theoretical structure for what the title calls the “basic liberties” that Americans legitimately expect to be protected in the 21st century, which very much includes reproductive choice. Interestingly enough, he derives his theory not from looking, say, at academic theorists—though he is certainly aware of contemporary arguments within the legal academy—but from very close analysis of basic Supreme Court cases. More than many legal academics these days (including myself), Fleming takes very seriously the opinions delivered by a wide variety of justices over the past century. He reads their opinions very carefully and draws from them a coherent theory of substantive due process that protects a variety of important liberties. Some readers may be surprised to discover that his judicial hero, in many ways, is not, say, William J. Brennan or Earl Warren, but, rather, John Marshall Harlan, who on notable occasions, including the reapportionment cases, dissented from quintessential “Warren Court” decisions. But Harlan wrote an opinion in a case involving Connecticut’s ban on contraceptives, dismissed on technical grounds, which he then incorporated into an eloquent concurring opinion in the famous case of Griswold v. Connecticut that invalidated the ban. Though William O. Douglas, for the majority, evoked the “penumbras and emanations” of the texts of several amendments within the Bill of Rights, Harlan, who viewed himself both as a conservative and as a traditionalist, rejected Douglas’s ostensibly textual argument in favor of one that emphasized the importance of American political and legal traditions. But Harlan importantly emphasized that tradition is “a living thing,” not ossified in any given past instantiation. It is up to judges to be sensitive to developments in this living tradition and, when need be, to write its teachings into concrete law. Thus he easily supported striking down Connecticut’s regulations on supplying methods of contraception even to married couples, even as Hugo Black dissented because the Constitution did not explicitly offer a textual protection of privacy. For Harlan that was (properly) irrelevant. Harlan offered a model of what University of Chicago law professor David Strauss calls “common-law constitutionalism.” Building on Harlan’s central insight, Fleming offers a painstaking analysis of what might be called the “canon” of cases, going back to the 1920’s, that find various libertarian protections in the Due Process Clause and create what John Hart Ely labeled the oxymoronic doctrine of “substantive due process” (as distinguished from a theory that would ask only if limitations on basic liberties had been adopted through proper procedures of, say, majority vote and then signature by the governor or president). Fleming is not naïve. He is well aware that the current Court is controlled by a majority totally unlikely to be sympathetic to his approach, as illustrated, obviously, is the Dobbs decision. But what he is doing, in essence, is creating the scaffolding of what might increasingly be termed the liberal “constitution in exile,” awaiting restoration when liberal Democrats are appointed (and confirmed) to the Supreme Court and can therefore eviscerate the mistakes of the current majority in just the same way that the current majority is happy to do with regard to decisions by its predecessors (often describing those decisions as “wrong the day they were decided,” which almost necessarily entails the suggestion that their authors were either knaves or fools). Political conservatives beginning in the 1980s often spoke of their own “constitution in exile,” and many devoted themselves to creating theories—including “originalism”—that could be drawn on when the exile came to an end. They are no doubt gratified by recent developments, and one can only hope that Fleming can achieve some of the same satisfaction in the future similar to that now felt by many conservatives. But it is at this point that I want to veer in a “meta direction,” away from any specific analysis of Fleming’s particular argument, built in some ways on the insights of Ronald Dworkin but far better developed, precisely because of its careful attention to actual cases, than anything ever written by Dworkin. Instead, I want to return to Tribe’s essay and its relevance to Fleming’s own project. It is worth quoting him at some length: Whether or not one sees Dobbs as barely concealed theocracy, what seems plain is that the opinion fails to provide any clear secular support for its conclusion that Roe was wrongly decided, much less that it was so demonstrably wrong that the reliance of generations of Americans on its basic outlines should have been all but entirely disregarded. That degree of certitude and hubris can only contribute to the growing lack of respect for the current Supreme Court and feed the mounting conviction that it is not a body composed of fair-minded jurists to whom we should entrust these kinds of questions (emphasis added).I think that, increasingly, the most important question one can ask is whether “we” (however defined) genuinely believe in the possibility of identifying a stunningly small number of lawyers who will be accepted as “fair-minded jurists to whom we should entrust” the kinds of questions that are entailed in debates about abortion, freedom of religion, sexual identity (and freedom), and access to guns. Two things would appear to be necessary: The first is to identify what one means by “fair-minded.” Ironically or not, Earl Warren was (in)famous for often asking lawyers in particular cases whether the positions they were taking were “fair.” For many, that represented a refreshing move away from a kind of legal formalism that asked only if they were “authorized” (a strictly procedural view of due process) in favor of directing our attention to the concrete implications for living individuals of the arguments being offered the Court. Detractors, on the other hand, including his former law clerk John Hart Ely, viewed this as basically sentimental, inviting judges to impose their own views of “fairness” on the body politic. He thus expressed reservations about Griswold and then wrote a savage attack on Roe even though he supported reproductive choice politically. The debate in many ways goes back to Justice Holmes’s typically cryptic dissenting opinion in Lochner v. New York: [The Constitution] is made for people of fundamentally differing views, and the accident of our finding certain opinions natural and familiar, or novel, and even shocking, ought not to conclude our judgment upon the question whether statutes embodying them conflict with the Constitution of the United States…. I think that the word 'liberty,' in the 14th Amendment, is perverted when it is held to prevent the natural outcome of a dominant opinion, unless it can be said that a rational and fair man necessarily would admit that the statute proposed would infringe fundamental principles as they have been understood by the traditions of our people and our law.There is an obvious tension between the recognition that we live within a pluralistic society defined by the existence of “fundamentally differing views” as to what constitutes the good life—and the role, if any, of particular rights in helping to achieve any given notion of a good life—and the assertion that there do exist “fundamental principles as they have been understood by the traditions of our people and our law.” To the extent that one believes in both the existence and knowability of such “fundamental principles,” then one will be sympathetic as well to the proposition that discrete judges can both discern and implement them. If, on the other hand, one is more impressed by a picture of American society as consisting, for better or worse, of groups with “fundamentally differing” and often incommensurable views who may be deeply appalled by the evil or decadent views posited by their adversaries, then why would one think that judges are likely to bring any resolution to such debates? And would any such success depend on a widespread and informed perception that the judges were now applying the “right” theory of interpretation, as distinguished from the presumptively dubious ones articulated in the now happily overruled decisions? It is, I think, this second question that makes one wonder not only about the likely audience for Fleming’s arguments, but also about the practical possibility of his teachings being generally accepted should the happy day come when Democratic presidents will appoint nominees who will proudly proclaim that they read and agreed with Constructing Basic Liberties. I return to Tribe once more, this time with regard to his famous 2005 letter to Justice Stephen Breyer, elaborated in a further 13-page explanation, as to why Tribe was abandoning his long-time project of writing a definitive “treatise” on American constitutional law that would truly rival that of Justice Joseph Story in the 1830s. Tribe had completed a first edition at the end of the 1970s, as well as a later second edition. But he then embarked on a much fuller revised version—until he abruptly stopped in 2005. Why did he stop? As he explained to Breyer, Tribe now saw only a ''seemingly irreconcilable division within legal and popular culture that is not amenable to the treatment that a treatise might hope to give such cases." “Constitutional law” (or theory) requires not only the setting out of an argument. It also requires, as a matter of social fact, a willingness of the relevant publics in general—whether professional, as within the legal academy, or elite opinion leaders, such as editorial writers for our major newspapers and other journals, or, ultimately, the general public, perhaps influenced by a variety of would be leaders—to accept the holdings of the judges, or at the very least to be “good sports” should they disagree and accept the law as handed down. Even in 2005, Tribe saw only “irreconcilable division,” as revealed in ever-more-common 5-4 decisions featuring angry and basically disrespectful dissents from the decidedly unhappy losers. Justice Scalia, for example, accused his colleagues of not “acting like judges” in their decision validating same-sex marriage in Obergefell v. Hodges. If one took that seriously, then his colleagues in the majority should have been impeached, for surely it should constitute the opposite of the “good behavior” accepted of judges that they no longer “act like judges” and instead simply impose their own personal preferences on the rest of us. Today, in a world of Facebook (Meta) and almost countless other forms of social media, together with a far more vitriolic and polarized political party structure, the socio-political consensus necessary for judicial legitimation seems more and more evanescent. The polarization of the Court is at least partially reflective of the highly polarized two-party system at the present time. For the first time in our history, there is no significant overlap in the votes of Democratic and Republican justices in the most contentious cases that come before the Supreme Court. Barry Friedman, in his 2009 book The Will of the People argued that the Court, generally speaking, came surprisingly close to mirroring the actual preferences of the American public. The so-called “median” justices, first Sandra Day O’Connor and then Anthony Kennedy, were, Friedman argued, close to the so-called “median voter. Both liberals and conservatives would applaud or object to given votes of these justices, but they were rarely perceived as wildly out of step. But now the “median justice” is probably Brett Kavanaugh, given that Chief Justice John Roberts is increasingly a leader without any dependable followers, as revealed in his lonely concurrence in Dobbs, rejected by his conservative and liberal colleagues alike. If it is true, as some political scientists argue, that the American public at large is less polarized than are public officials elected through the current party system, then perhaps one or two replacements on the current Court would restore the kind of acceptance evoked by Tribe. But one might doubt the likelihood of this happening, at least in the foreseeable future. The American political scientist Jim Gibson gave a talk at the University of Texas some years ago that had a deep impact on my own thought. In it, he explained that the Supreme Court’s ultimate power rested on what political scientists term “diffuse support,” i.e., a willingness to accept whatever decisions come down from the Court. This required paying no attention to the actual reasoning supporting such decisions. After all, extraordinarily few people, including lawyers, actually read the opinions. As he explained it, with regard to those few hot-button issues that actually reach public notice, 35% (let us assume) may support the decision, while another 35% are heatedly opposed. But support and opposition will be based on agreement or disagreement with the policies thought to be adopted (or invalidated) by the Court. But that leaves 30% who will respond to polls, according to Gibson, by saying “the job of the Court is to make tough decisions, and I’m not willing to criticize them for coming out as they did. They’re smarter than I am and know more about the law. They ruled, and is it the job of good Americans to back the ruling.” So what this means, practically speaking, is that the Court can (or could) rely on majority support for anything it does, where the majority is constituted both by those who affirmatively endorse the decision and those who offer the Court diffuse support. More recently, however, Gibson has written a major paper, based on polling data following Dobbs, suggesting that “diffuse support” for the Court has collapsed. Just as we no longer expect many Americans to accept any given presidential decision because, after all, it’s “the President,” surrounded by smart advisors, who believes we need to do X, it’s no longer clear that the Court should expect to benefit from institutional diffuse support. Thus the most recent polling by the Pew Charitable Trust indicates that 49% of the public has an “unfavorable view” of the Court, while 48% remain positive in their overall views. Other polls show similar or worse results (from the perspective of the current majority). Increasingly, it appears that most Americans are inclined to view justices as “politicians in robes” rather than as Tribe’s “fair-minded jurists to whom we should entrust these kinds of questions.” Dworkin famously described the Court as the distinctive “forum of principle,” in contrast to the presumably distasteful “political” branch particularly of the Congress. Most contemporary Americans, including many legal academics, are having an increasingly hard time telling the difference. So what would it take for a Court to be able successfully to impose a Flemingesque or Tribean vision of the Constitution? Justice Scalia famously suggested that it took a theory to beat a theory, and he suggested that “living constitutionalism” was theoretically weak, unable to surmount “originalism.” John Hart Ely elaborated a theory, which he called “representation reinforcement,” but, as already suggested, he had no sympathy for reading certain rights into the Constitution through the Due Process Clause. Tribe, in fact, notably attacked his colleague’s book as being much too proceduralist. Fleming now offers a carefully elaborated—and, surely, to many of “us,” convincing—theory of “basic liberties.” But the reason for the scare quotes around “us” is precisely my concern that this book, even if it is widely read, as it should be, will ultimately preach only to the already existing choir. Randy Barnett, Richard Epstein, and Michael Greve, to name only three notable conservative academics, did not succeed in bringing their version of the Constitution out of its exile because they persuaded a lot of general readers that their “liberal constitutionalism” was mistaken. Instead, they worked closely with well-organized movements within the legal academy—most notably the Federalist Society—and within the general polity and waited, in effect, for their time to come, which it most certainly did with the election of Donald Trump and the absolute devotion of Mitch McConnell and the Republican majority in the Senate to capturing control of the federal judiciary by any means necessary. Theirs was a political victory, not an admission of defeat by former adversaries who were in fact persuaded that we must all be originalists now or accept the illegitimacy of the administrative state because of dogmatic theories of “separation of powers.” As we should have learned after Appomattox, surrender on the battlefield does not mean that “hearts and minds” have necessarily changed with regard to the most fundamental underlying issues generating the battle, in that case the preservation of white supremacy. For most people on the left (including myself), the current Supreme Court majority is basically as “stolen,” in terms of the integrity of the process by which they got their lifetime jobs, as many people on the right believe (falsely, of course) to be the case with Joe Biden’s having become president. A last bit of quotation, this time from my own work, the 1988 edition of my book Constitutional Faith. (A second edition, published in 2011, explained why I had lost my own faith in the U.S. Constitution, but that’s another topic.) I concluded chapter one by noting that It is ironic that a culture that has experienced what Matthew Arnold over a century ago described as a ‘melancholy, long-withdrawing roar’ from traditional religious faith can assert the continuing reality of a collectivity of citizens organized around a constitutional faith. The ‘death of constitutionalism’ may be the central event of our time, just as the “death of God” was that of the past century (and for much the same reason). Many in our culture have neither belief in the persuasive force of detached reason nor the ability to make a ‘leap of faith’ upon reaching the barriers of rational assent. The fact that the public rhetoric of American political culture remains organized, in substantial ways, as a faith community centered on the Constitution may mislead us as to the health of that culture. After all, as the senior Oliver Wendell Holmes reminded us in the “One-Hoss Shay,” a thinly disguised parable about classical Calvinism, a once-strong, indeed culturally dominant, mode of thought can collapse almost literally overnight.We are not, I think, faced with the prospect that the Supreme Court, or the rest of the judiciary, will simply collapse. After all, most cases are of no interest to anyone other than the litigants, and it is essential to the workings of the social order that litigants be able to turn to more-or-less neutral (or perhaps better described as truly “indifferent”) adjudicators to resolve their disputes (and to be “good losers” if need be). This is why even countries identified as undoubtedly authoritarian may have relatively “independent judiciaries” at least with regard to some areas of law, such as the enforcement of business contracts. But books like Fleming’s are not responses to the ordinary “private-law” cases decided by the judiciary. Rather, he is concerned with a distinct subset of cases that many people really do care about, often encouraged to do so by politically motivated “issue entrepreneurs” who see in the judiciary a useful issue around which to mobilize upset political bases. We are often likely to identify a “blockbuster” term of the Supreme Court by reference to literally no more than half a dozen of the roughly 60-70 cases it now decides during a typical year. And most works of “constitutional theory” concentrate on the issues raised by that minority of cases. During the upcoming term, this includes, in particular, affirmative action and the use of race in public decisionmaking as well as the freedom of “independent state legislatures” in essence to ignore their own state constitutions—and the opinions of state supreme courts—with regard to structuring elections. And, inevitably, there will be more cases examining the extent to which religious commitments entitle one to the “basic liberty” of exemption from following general state laws that apply to everyone else. What some call the “crisis of judicial legitimacy” has little to do with preserving some kind of “independent” judiciary in a wide variety of cases. Rather, it has everything to do with the willingness of the general public to accept the kind of “common-law constitutionalism” valorized by Fleming, which depends in turn on acceptance of the wisdom and insights of those lawyers who become Justices, whether John Marshall Harlan, Thurgood Marshall, Clarence Thomas, Samuel Alito, or Ketanji Brown Jackson. So will the future return us to the halcyon days of “good sportsmanship” and acceptance of defeats? Or will the “melancholy, long-witdrawing roar” of a declining constitutional faith become ever louder and lead us to a much more radical revisioning of what we seek from the Supreme Court and its members? Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |