E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
This post was prepared for a roundtable onComparative
Constitutional Design, convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022—a
year-long series gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to
reflect on Sandy Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. Gary Jacobsohn Twenty-five years ago Sandy contributed an essay to a book I
co-edited on citizenship in which he began with a reflection on pedagogy that
is recognizably Levinsonian. “Perhaps the most basic lesson of teaching,” he
wrote, “is that the learning process can work two ways, and it is not always
easy to distinguish the teachers from the taught.” In this particular essay
Sandy was addressing the lawyer/citizen problem, namely whether a state—Connecticut
was one that had done so—could limit membership to the bar to “loyal
Americans,” individuals who were not associated by membership or propagation with
“subversive” ideas. The issue had arisen for discussion in a seminar with
Eastern European lawyers, a group whose members Sandy thought would benefit
from exposure to a liberal academic lawyer’s reflections on the American
experience. It will come as no surprise that Sandy opposed the
Connecticut policy, a stance that found him in agreement with the Supreme
Court. And true to his pedagogical musings, that he could see his way to understanding
why a political test for limiting legal practice was in certain instances
justifiable is also not surprising. In an exchange with a Latvian lawyer who
defended a citizenship requirement, he was left wondering if “the specific
circumstances of Latvia” required a reassessment of her “tribal parochialism,”
one that “might have implications even for our own, very different, political
situation here in the United States.” This then led to some predictably
thoughtful ruminations about small vulnerable societies, settings where
cultural preservation might sensibly be seen as taking precedence over liberal
universalism. As they say, so far so good. But then this: “Perhaps I should
note that I know almost nothing about the actual system of Latvian law…. To the
extent that specific facts matter, I exercise the prerogative of law professors
to stipulate them when convenient for my argument.” The candor is surely
laudable as a refreshingly uncommon example of academic humility, yet does it
not compel one to be skeptical of some of what Sandy had to say in the essay,
especially if, like me, you fancy yourself a fact-based scholar of constitutional
issues in faraway places? More generally, the question of how much knowledge
about a country other than one’s own is sufficient for generating valuable
insights about that country’s constitutional order is what I want to address in
these remarks. The safest answer to the epistemological question would
follow from the teachings of anthropology, where expressive meanings are only
cognizable within a specific interpretive setting, where, as Clifford Geertz
pointed out, “the ability to construe…modes of expression” requires deep
engagement with the other. The anthropologist’s ethnographic methods have a trans-disciplinary
appeal; hence the appearance of an approach to the study of foreign legal
systems known as “constitutional ethnography.” As defined by Kim Scheppele, it
is “the study of the central legal elements of polities using methods that are
capable of recovering the lived detail of the politico-legal landscape.” As she
also makes clear, this intense engagement with the details of a given polity does
not mean that the knowledge obtained from such an inquiry extends no further
than its originating source. After all, an “urgent issue” in comparative
constitutional studies is to advance an understanding of one’s own
constitutional experience through knowledge of another’s. Or as Alexis de
Tocqueville wrote, “It is not…merely to satisfy a curiosity, however
legitimate, that I have examined America; my wish has been to find there
instruction by which we may ourselves profit.” Indeed, Tocqueville can help us think through the problem at
hand. His visit to the United States clearly checks the box of Geertzian deep
engagement with the other, and even if his extended trip did not have as its
main focus “the central legal elements” of American society, he probably said
enough about public law related matters to qualify as a constitutional
ethnographer. [Indeed, Tocqueville wrote at great length about the American
Constitution. Anticipating Levinson, he wrote: “It can happen that a minority
of the nation, dominating the Senate, entirely paralyzes the will of the
majority…which is contrary to the spirit of constitutional governments.”] The
knowledge he acquired surely fulfilled the purpose of providing timely and profitable
instruction for his countrymen; in the long term no doubt even greater illumination
for generations of Americans. But what exactly was it that Tocqueville knew that was
of most value to his readers? Was it the deep immersion in a particular
cultural and social milieu that generated his instructive discernments? Was it
only that immersion that led him to his most definitive conclusion about
American law? “When one wants to speak of the political laws of the United
States, it is always with the dogma of the sovereignty of the people that one
must begin.” To be sure, generative or not, it would be odd to think of his
singular direct exposure as unrelated to the quality of the insights. Still,
consider this. Although Tocqueville never visited India, he fully grasped the
enormity of its challenges. “India cannot be civilized as long as she conserves
her religion and her religion is so intermingled with the structure of its
social state, of its customs and of its laws, that one does not know how to
destroy it.” His account of a religiously based feudalism was tinged with a
dark pessimism, the poignancy of which is underscored by his experience as a
direct observer of a feudal order that had been destroyed. He did not imagine a
constitutionally grounded deliverance from this sad predicament in a place he
knew only from a distance, but a century later the leading Indian
constitutional designers invoked the same foundational premise to create a
“civilized,” if imperfect, regime. Which brings me back to Sandy, with whom I have had the
privilege of co-teaching a seminar on comparative constitutionalism. In a
recent look back at that collaboration, he echoed his Latvia remark of twenty-five
years earlier. While claiming to lack “a requisite degree of genuine knowledge
that entitles me to make any very confident pronouncements about given foreign
constitutional systems,” he proceeded to articulate a strong pedagogical
rationale for what he could contribute to the occasion. “My comparative
advantage in discussions of world constitutions is to push the conversation
toward the United States Constitution.” Setting aside my own clear
recollections of pronouncements that seemed extremely well informed by
requisite knowledge, there is something very Tocquevillian about this remark, as
arguably the Frenchman’s comparative advantage was his capacity for producing
trans-nationally derived insights that were germane to the constitutional
condition of his home country. Those reflections, however, were set against a backdrop of
philosophical acumen and cross-cultural curiosity, without which the
comparative advantage becomes illusory. In Sandy’s case, what he recently
opined should be paired with another thought from that essay from twenty-five
years ago. “Whether discussing Connecticut, Canada, or Latvia, one must pay
close attention to context in determining the relevance of citizenship to such
social roles as lawyering.” That sentence was also the essay’s final words; to
underscore what is ultimately most valuable to the knowledge question in the
study of comparative public law requires only a brief elaboration. A contextual
rendering of citizenship, or for that matter Church/State relations, or hate
speech (to name just a couple of obvious issues) must take into account the
aspirations and commitments that have a connection to the more particular constitutive
features of individual polities. So think again about Latvia, as it exists today, bordered to
its east by Russia, to its southeast by Belarus, and in close proximity to
Ukraine, with whom it shares a Soviet-era history. Russians in Latvia
constitute 25% of its population, more than 50% in Riga, the nation’s capital. Latvian
is the only official language, a policy overwhelmingly upheld ten years ago in
a constitutional referendum. By contrast, there is no official language in the
United States, although some thirty states have designated English to be just
that. How should one think about this linguistic conundrum, specifically how
might the “comparative advantage” illuminate the question? Assume that the question called for an assessment of Latvia’s
language policy. Tocquevillian comparative advantage methodology begins with a
depiction of the aristocratic condition (for example, “The aristocratic
constitution influences the ideas and mores of servants scarcely less than
those of masters….”), then proceeds with an analysis of how the problem ought
to be understood in that other place, where, as in the United States, a
contrasting explanatory perspective, the equality of condition, prevails. In
Sandy’s case, he might begin with the not uncontroversial supposition that the
United States is a multicultural polity, a point he has made against the
contrary “one people” claim of John Jay in Federalist #2, and has also
made in the essay on the lawyer as citizen. Like Canada, which, it should be
said, is officially multicultural, the US is an immigrant society. The familiar
melting pot metaphor to the contrary notwithstanding, an alternative assimilative
model that clearly favors the official national prioritizing of English is, I
presume, anathema to Sandy. So having pushed the conversation in an American
direction, what should be said about Latvia? Again, context is everything. What situational concern would
support a decision by the state of Connecticut to adopt English as its official
language? Is its cultural identity being threatened by New York and Massachusetts?
If constitutionally mandated multiculturalism in Canada requires official
national recognition of English and French, does not that same constitutional
identity oblige deference to Quebec’s linguistic act of cultural
self-preservation? And would not the same logic that Sandy has applied to
lawyering apply to the language question? To wit: “Small, vulnerable societies,
concerned to preserve (or restore) a particularistic culture against the
perceived threat of being overwhelmed by cultural outsiders, might legitimately
reach different conclusions from our own about the attributes deemed desirable in
those who would practice law.” To be sure, the cosmopolitan logic of liberal
constitutionalism offers a strong counter-argument to this particularism; when
applied, for example, to the “illiberal constitutionalism” of, say, Hungary it
convincingly reaches a different outcome. But, alas, Latvia is not Hungary. It’s one thing to worry
about preserving a cultural identity, quite another to agonize about losing
one’s very physical identity. Affirming that identity constitutionally (or at
least through ordinary law) is defensible, even if its wisdom is debatable; i.e.,
why give the Russians another pretext for making your country another Ukraine? And
then there’s the additional question—about which I am quite ambivalent—as to
how such a policy might affect the enlightenment project of constitutionalism
if its justification is predicated on purely pragmatic concerns. Indeed, what
Sandy said about the Latvian prohibition of noncitizen lawyers applies here as
well, which is that while its underlying rationale may not generate support for
the policy, it does not lead unambiguously to a condemnation. So, to return to the question of how much knowledge about a
country other than one’s own is sufficient for earning a respectful hearing
about such matters. Law
incorporates an aspect that comparative inquiry reveals as ubiquitous, namely a
need to convey meaning about features of the legal system that are expressive
of a specific homegrown identity, and those attributes that are part of a more
or less common stock of aspirations we have come to associate with the generic
practice of law. It confronts one with the
diversity of national experiences in constitutional governance, but it also
makes one aware of general properties that, to varying degrees, serve to mark
constitutions as distinguishable entities of a certain type. These become the
chapters of the larger story we tell about the law that entails
reconciling the particularistic commitments of local traditions and practices
with our obligation to pursue a path in the law that brings us to a place that
satisfies expectations concerning a universal sense of justice. Comparativists
are wise to include a diverse group of fellow travelers along that path: among
the included, the ethnographer deeply immersed in the study of one or two
constitutional orders, and the large-N investigator whose limited contextual
knowledge should not deflect from the knowledge of larger tendencies in
constitutionalism that are attainable through her efforts. But there should be
room as well for the philosophically learned individual whose comparative
advantage is rooted in his knowledge base meticulously fashioned from an
intense engagement with sources within the
domestic constitutional environment; who asks, if there are attributes of a
constitutional order that are taken to be essential for constitutionalism to
exist in more than name only, then would it not be sensible to look beyond
resident boundaries to seek validation or disapprobation of prevailing
arrangements? Gary Jacobsohn is Professor of Government and
Professor of Law at the University of Texas at Austin. You can contact him at gjacobsohn@austin.utexas.edu.