Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts E Unum Pluribus: Comparative Textualism & Constitutional Faiths
|
Tuesday, August 02, 2022
E Unum Pluribus: Comparative Textualism & Constitutional Faiths
Guest Blogger
This post was prepared for a
roundtable on Wrestling with
Religious Diversity, convened as part of LevinsonFest 2022—a
year-long series gathering scholars from diverse disciplines and viewpoints to
reflect on Sandy Levinson’s influential work in constitutional law. Intisar
A. Rabb From one text comes many interpretations: e
unum pluribus. This formula is of course an inversion of e pluribus unum
(“from many, one”)—the motto for American democracy emblazoned on our money
to provide as often a reminder to [property-owning] adherents of America’s
“civil religion” of shared constitutional ideals, constitutional aspirations, constitutional
faiths.[1] By making faiths
plural, I am in part ceding the about-face that Sandy Levinson, former
adherent, made in his Foreword to a new edition of his book Constitutional
Faith. There, he concluded that, although the Constitution’s generalities
are still fluid and thus negotiable, many of its structural elements have
settled in ways that make governance and addressing problems of injustice hard.[2]
The Supreme Court’s Term this year perhaps proves the point.[3] Taking
up Sandy’s charge that scholars rarely discuss the general elements that make
interpretation hard, I offer some comparative perspective from a seemingly
unlikely place—Islam’s pluralistic legal system—to suggest that in any legal
interpretation, including the most controversial in the U.S., difficult interpretive
elements are never about a single constitutional faith. Nor are they even about
religion, per se, even when they seem to be. They are about a plurality of
constitutional faiths despite a single legal text. Those elements motivate core
differences in the Court’s interpretive debates over fundamental privileges
versus promises, textualism versus purposivism, status quo-preserving
originalism vs. rights-promoting pragmatism.[4] I
aim to explore those elements with an eye to the plurality of opinions that
emerge from shared legal texts, now that stare decisis is in question as
a way to settle them and now that interpretations of history and tradition
matter a lot toward the same end. Consider
Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, the Court’s recent
decision overturning its 1973 decision Roe v. Wade and its companion
1992 decision Planned Parenthood v. Casey.[5]
Differing interpretive approaches and conclusions in its majority and
dissenting opinions display competing visions of “history and tradition.”[6]
Those competing visions reflexively drive the interpretive approaches that
dictate which history and which traditions to adopt—in Dobbs,
a supermajority adopted an originalism that somehow excluded the history of
slavery and its ongoing consequences, as well as the Constitution’s
Reconstruction Amendments meant to address it, as Professor Michelle
Goodwin has powerfully pointed out.[7]
And both sides reveal competing accounts of the otherwise agreed-upon common
law doctrine of stare decisis and when to forego it. In the end, all of
these disagreements about history and interpretive method reveal differing
value commitments in the guise of competing beliefs, not explicitly in
religious faith (despite its obvious relevance to abortion),[8]
but in the Constitution and the role of the Court: that is, competing constitutional
faiths, plural.[9] As
with the popular religious and political polarization about abortion,
interpretive polarization was evident in the questions presented before the
Court, with no room for nuance, discussion, or compromise. Each side was at
pains to point out that only one position should and could reign supreme, and Justice
Alito was happy to oblige in Dobbs.[10]
But in reality, on the court, judges must wrestle with diversity.[11] In
short, and as Dobbs exemplifies, interpretive disagreement on the Court
is less often about religious difference in the traditional sense than it is
about civil religious differences and a plurality of constitutional faiths. To
be sure, it is not that religion is irrelevant to the question. Far from it.
The popular and political frameworks surrounding the “right to life,” and
sometimes even the “right to choose,” are either inspired by or put in the
language of different religious worldviews about the start and sacredness of
life or religious freedom, and the religious-moral limitations on curtailing
either.[12]
Since Dobbs (both the leaked draft and the final opinion), American
Muslims have responded in spades about the diversity of Islamic law positions
on when life begins and prior questions of
sexual propriety within marriage, when abortion is thus plausibly valid, and
the extent to which anti-abortion legislation—without exceptions—may impinge on
their constitutional right to free exercise as a result.[13]
But I do not seek to resolve the debates about religion and abortion; they are
somewhat marginal to the Court’s decision, which is by no means a religious
establishment/free exercise case. To wit: despite that public religion
discourse surrounding abortion, the Dobbs Court analysis took religion
as so marginal to its analysis that the term, on its own, never actually
appears in its opinions.[14]
Rather, the question I’m concerned with here is whether or how we might think
about doctrines (especially with the questions placed on stare decisis) that
might better recognize a diversity of opinions even if one reigns supreme,
while ensuring the rule of law. For this, I wish to look at the idea of
constitutional faiths and comparative textualism. In
considering how American judges approach statutory interpretation with appeal
to constitutional faith(s), several questions arise immediately: constitutional
faith in what? Should our faith lay in constitutional structure or rights, in
originalism or evolving societal understandings and commitments, in procedural
or substantive norms? How does better recognition of interpretive pluralism and
judicial choice help resolve the formal-moral dilemma? In this short essay, I
don’t seek to answer those questions, but I do seek to uncover the significance
of asking them. I
will proceed, in Part I, with examples of pluralistic statutory interpretation
using common legal canons in American law. I will next examine, in Part II,
interpretive pluralism in Islamic law and spotlight an important legal canon
that medieval Muslim jurists devised to accommodate that pluralism. Finally, in
Part III, I will conclude with a return to our initial questions for American
law: having considered canons that guide interpretive pluralism from another
system and reflect different ‘faiths’, how might American jurists better
accommodate the fact that statutory interpretation is a pluralistic exercise,
and what does that mean for modern notions of constitutional faith(s)? First,
consider the use of legal canons, which leads to interpretive pluralism in
American statutory interpretation, even on a majority textualist Supreme Court.
Today’s justices make generous use of legal canons—those old principles of
interpretation that come from Roman law and are often, perhaps surprisingly,
shared with Islamic law.[15]
After Karl Llewelyn excoriated the use of these legal canons to interpret
statutes as incoherent over half a century ago, Justice Scalia and his
textualist colleagues (and disciples) rehabilitated them.[16]
They are now favored tools for Justices Barrett, Kavanaugh, Gorsuch, Alito,
Roberts, and Thomas. For that matter, Justices Breyer, Kagan, and Sotomayor, as
well as Justice Brown Jackson (while a federal judge), use those canons with
increasing frequency in statutory interpretation cases as well.[17]
Recognizing that fact, Justice Elena Kagan and a leading nontextualist scholar
of statutory interpretation, Professor William Eskridge, have quipped, “[w]e’re
all textualists now” (well, before walking that statement back in dissent to
this past Term’s environmental protection case).[18]
For interpreting statutes, our “most fundamental semantic rule of
interpretation,” according to textualists Justice Antonin Scalia and Bryan
Garner,[19]
and interpretation’s “prime directive,” in the words of Prof. Eskridge is the ordinary
meaning canon: the requirement to interpret statutes according to their
plain or ordinary meaning.[20] The
agreed-upon ordinary meaning canon produces multiple interpretations,
and it manages to divide textualists from one another. Take the interpretive
pluralism that emerged among textualists applying that canon in Bostock v.
Clayton County (2020).[21]
Writing for the majority, Justice Neil Gorsuch used the ordinary meaning
canon to extend Title VII’s prohibition of discrimination “on the basis of
sex” to include sexual orientation and gender identity. In dissent, Justice
Brett Kavanaugh (writing separately from two other dissenting textualist
justices), rejected that application of ordinary meaning (though not the
canon or the text of the statute itself); he further advocated applying another
canon to inform ordinary meaning itself: the rule against superfluity,
which would avoid rendering the phrase “sexual orientation” in other
statutes superfluous. That
same ordinary meaning canon produces interpretive pluralism that divides
nontextualists from one another as well. Consider the now infamous case, United
States v. Muscarello from two decades ago. In 1998, the Court appealed to
the ordinary meaning canon to determine whether a firearms statute that
imposed a sentencing enhancement for anyone who “carries a firearm” in the
course of a drug trafficking crime applied to a man who had a gun in his locked
glove compartment on the way to a drug sale.[22]
Writing for the majority, Justice Stephen Breyer concluded that “carries”
simply meant to transport or convey from one place to another,
and thus upheld the enhancement imposed on Mr. Muscarello, who had a gun in a
locked glove compartment on his way to drug sale.[23]
In dissent, Justice Ruther Bader Ginsburg (whom Justice Scalia joined),
rejected the majority interpretation in favor of a contextual reading of the
phrase “carries a firearm” (not just “carries” alone) to mean “packing heat”—
that is, that the whole phrase, pertains to firearms that are both
transported and readily accessible in the course of a drug transaction. [24]
She added that the fact of the majority’s disagreement and the indeterminacy of
interpretive aids to resolve it left a lingering ambiguity that was to be
resolved with another substantive legal canon that has constitutional
foundations: the rule of lenity.[25]
That venerable rule directs courts faced with ambiguity in criminal statutes to
adopt the narrower meaning, in favor of the defendant.[26] In
both cases, interpretive ambiguity remained. Constitutional faith, as if a
single belief, did not resolve it. All agreed on the singular constitution, and
the singular statutory text. But competing visions of the Constitution’s
structure and rights requirements and in the Court’s role in preserving them
through statutory interpretation yielded each judgment and each dissent. Each
faithfully adhered to different interpretive approached lodged in their
different constitutional faiths. Next,
we turn to Islamic law to consider related legal canons that exemplify
interpretive pluralism and how a contrastive legal system approached it in a
very different system from our own. To begin with, it is worth pointing out
that Islamic law has some of the same textualist canons as does American law.
For example, it has its own ordinary meaning canon: judges are to apply
the plain and ordinary meaning of the text (ẓāhir) unless contextual
clues indicate otherwise. That canon yields its own interpretive pluralism,
with majority and minority groups of jurists disagreeing about the ordinary
meaning of a single text.[27]
But for purposes of illustrating a comparative approach to questions of
interpretive pluralism, here, I want to focus on another legal canon in Islamic
law that attempts to recognize and address the fact of that pluralism in a
system without a Supreme Court and thus without a final say at any one point in
history in a system that nevertheless used interpretation to maintain the rule
of law of historically. What
we might label Islamic law’s interpretive pluralism canon says
that “one interpretation cannot be overturned by another interpretation: al-ijtihād
lā yunqaḍ biʾl-ijtihād.” A corollary, that “every interpreter is correct: kull
mujtahid muṣīb,” suggests that there is no right answer, or if there is,
that knowledge of it lies only with the divine.[28]
Muslim jurists asserted that interpreters receive a reward for the interpretive
exercise itself (and doubly so if they get it right—but only in the afterlife,
as the morally correct answer is known only to God and must therefore be
subject to constant deliberation and negotiation by interpreters of law with
differing approaches). These same Muslim jurists asserted that ordinary
subjects and citizens are duty-bound to follow the dictates of recognized
Islamic laws, even when they are choosing many rulings on a singular same
issue. In short, Muslim jurists took morality to be an unknown ideal that must
be pursued anew with every new interpretation and every new understanding; that
fact required them to recognize all interpretations that faithfully undergo a
sound interpretive process. These precepts work together to create what one
scholar calls Islam’s radical legal pluralism: “the ability to countenance
multiple interpretations as equally authoritative.”[29] What
does this have to do with constitutional faith? It is, in a word, plural. For
the Muslim faithful, Islamic legal pluralism translates into a certain
conviction (and doubt!) in the interpretive process that trained jurists
produce, against a backdrop of a divine-moral truth they may never know, but
that they must nevertheless keep trying to access in every encounter with
interpretation as understandings and societal circumstances evolve over time
and place. For judges applying the law, this legal pluralism thus readily
acknowledges that they must always be ready to choose between a range of
plausible interpretations—past and present. Doing so requires them to draw on
larger substantive-moral principles from Islam’s foundational texts and
practices that best apply to a particular case at hand as they understand
questions of fact and law with the benefit of deliberation and even comparative
insight. It is such insight that led modern jurists to declare slavery itself
contrary to Islamic law even though the Qurʾān itself once tacitly acknowledged
another version of it.[30]
For Muslim judges and jurists engaged in textual-legal interpretation, legal
pluralism supports religious or ‘constitutional’ faiths in both sound
interpretive processes and a moral ideal that they must constantly negotiate
even if they can never definitively say they have reached it. Finally,
we return to questions I raised at the outset with American law, in hopes that
the detour to questions of comparative textualism from Islamic law has thrown
into relief the centrality of interpretive pluralism and the importance of
identifying the ways judges tend to resolve it with respect to our own notions
of constitutional faith. The portrait of American interpretive pluralism from
cases applying a shared ordinary meaning canon to a singular statute is
just one example among scores of statutory interpretation cases from the U.S.
Supreme Court (which are only increasing, with the rise of textualism and the
attendant use of legal canons). That interpretive pluralism requires judges to
make choices between a range of plausible outcomes. As other scholars have
readily pointed out, that choice is never a purely text-based endeavor devoid
of substantive values. Instead, it typically appeals to a vision of the
Constitution and to the workings of other branches of government in modern
society. In other words, it is an appeal to a particular version of
constitutional faith, or put differently, a pluralistic version of it:
constitutional faiths. The
constitutional faith that any one interpreter adopts is heavily inflected with
notions of history and tradition (and with it, morality and justice) that they
take the Constitution to embody and to instruct judges on in turn. Textualist
visions of statutory originalism, for example, call up a vision of
constitutional history that claims that the Founders sought to preserve the
rule of law (and thus the status quo). This vision perceives that America’s constitutional
structure means that Article 1, § 7 supports a democracy-forcing value of
strong legislative deference and curtailed judicial interpretation that favors
narrow readings of statutory texts (notwithstanding congressional gridlock that
belies the ostensible reason for those narrow readings: to force a clear
statement from Congress if warranted). Contrary visions of constitutional
history and statutory purpose point out that legislation is an act that, by its
very nature, seeks to change the status quo for some purpose communicated
through the text of statutes. These visons also take the statutory text, for
similar Article 1, § 7 structural reasons, as a starting point. Yet, believers
in this second vision read the Founders (and the Constitution) to have imposed
on Article III judges a role that only they are constitutionally empowered and
institutionally best situated to fulfill: a duty to incorporate and negotiate
constitutional norms—including the structures and values alike that favor
legislative supremacy, individual rights, and democratic interests together. The
rise of legal canons in statutory interpretation on today’s Supreme Court means
that judicial interpreters now face a choice. Judges might choose the
constitutional faith in structure, originalism, and process that assumes away
reality or the need for negotiation to meet the hard demands of governance and
justice. Or they might choose a constitutional faith that begins with
constitutional structure and is open to negotiating how best to respond to
institutional realities, create checks and balances, and step into judicial
roles that best facilitate governance and justice. That vision easily includes
reconsidering channels of a now quiet court-congress dialogue that accommodates
congressional preferences and constitutional norms necessary to resolve
disputed statutory and constitutional questions. This latter conception of
faith is one that Islamic law judges did not (and could not) pursue. They
devised instead their own notion of God and of ‘constitutional’ faiths from
their foundational sources. If it is true, as I have suggested, that statutory
and constitutional interpretation frequently yields interpretive pluralism,
then it is worth delineating and debating to which of the constitutional faiths
judges will adhere, perhaps in every case and explicitly debating the right
interpretive methods to deploy. The question offers unique prospect for
advancing the promise of justice and American democracy. * * * My
central argument here has been that the inverted phrase, e unum pluribus,
provides a more accurate slogan for American legal interpretation than its
reverse. It prompts us to take seriously the notion that
judges
must often choose between a diverse set of plausible interpretations of
the same statutory or constitutional text. Moreover, I argue, this notion helps
us recognize that judges already make that choice with appeal to two different
types of constitutional faiths. In the proceeding discussion, I sought to
highlight as much through a comparative-and-contrastive foray into
interpretation in the very different system of classical Islamic law, which
recognizes pluralistic principles of diverse interpretations, and faiths,
forthrightly.[31] And I
suggest that, if stare decisis is on the chopping block in American law,
we might imagine a new set of canons that better support approaches to
interpretation and rule of law that accommodate plurality instead of
all-or-nothing approaches to history and tradition. In
the end, two competing visions of the history and society in statutory
interpretation suggest two different constitutional faiths. In almost every
decision, the Court debates how best to interpret the Constitution as American
scripture, as if the arbiters of America’s civil religion. My basic point is
that—whether the reader takes or leaves the comparative perspective—we might do
well to resolve recurring questions of interpretive pluralism from a single
statutory text (that is, e unum pluribus: from one, many), by
recognizing the pluralism of our constitutional faiths and more forthrightly
seeking to address essential questions of which one we believe in, and why. If
not stare decisis, comprehensive history and tradition, and other settled
expressions of constitutional faith, what are the new legal canons that drive
interpretation? Intisar
A. Rabb is Professor of Law, Professor of History, and Director of
the Program in Islamic Law at Harvard Law School. You can contact her via
luckau@law.harvard.edu. [1] See Sanford V. Levinson,
Constitutional Faith (2d ed. 2011) [orig. publ. 1988]. [2] Id.,
at 246–47. [3] For analysis of the most
controversial 6-3 cases this term, see Michael Macagnone, Supreme Court
Conservatives Flex in Term Full of Controversial Cases, Roll Call (Jun. 30, 2022) at https://rollcall.com/2022/06/30/supreme-court-conservatives-flex-in-term-full-of-controversial-cases/ (In 6-3 decisions along ideological
lines, the court this term ended the constitutional
right to an abortion, curtailed the power of states
to regulate the carrying of firearms in public, limited the power of federal
agencies to regulate greenhouse gas emissions and, in two cases, sided with religious liberty when it clashed with public schools.). For a full list of cases for the
2021 Term, see SCOTUSblog at https://www.scotusblog.com/case-files/terms/ot2021/. [4] One
fairly quick way of driving home the point is to consult the contrasting
treatises of the lead architects of these dueling interpretive theories,
together with references to judicial opinions exemplifying each in both
constitutional and statutory interpretation cited at length in each work.
Contrast Antonin Scalia & Bryan
Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal Texts (2012), with William N. Eskridge, Jr., Interpreting Law: A
Primer on how to Read Statutes and the Constitution (2016). [5] Dobbs
v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, 597 U. S. __ passim (2022). Roe
v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) recognized a constitutional right to obtain
abortion before third-trimester “viability” and other specific circumstances. Planned
Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992), relied on
stare decisis to uphold Roe and to restrict abortion regulations that
imposed any “undue burden.” [6] Dobbs,
597 U. S. __ passim (2022) (slip op., at *3, 5, 9, 12 and passim); id. at *12
(“In deciding whether a right falls into either of these categories [that is,
‘rights guaranteed by the first eight Amendments’ or ‘fundamental rights that
are not mentioned anywhere in the Constitution’], the Court has long asked
whether the right is ‘deeply rooted in [our] history and tradition’ and whether
it is essential to our Nation’s ‘scheme of ordered liberty.’”) (citing Timbs v.
Indiana, 586 U. S. __, __ (2019) (slip op., at 3)(internal quotation marks
omitted); McDonald v. Chicago, 561 U. S. 742, 764, 767 (2010) (internal
quotation marks omitted); Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702, 721 (1997)
(internal quotation marks omitted)). [7] No,
Justice Alito, Reproductive Justice Is in the Constitution, Wash. Post. (Jun. 26, 2022). See also Dobbs,
597 U.S. __, at *154–163 (Breyer, Sotomayor, and Kagan, JJ., dissenting) (slip
dissenting op., at 6–16) (detailing a competing narrative of America’s history
and traditions that root Roe and Casey in constitutional law and
the requirements of democracy that they positive the Court is charged to
uphold: “[T]his Court has rejected the majority’s pinched view of how to read
our Constitution. ‘The Founders,’ we recently wrote, ‘knew they were writing a
document designed to apply to ever-changing circumstances over centuries.’ Or
in the words of the great Chief Justice John Marshall, our Constitution is
‘intended to endure for ages to come,’ and must adapt itself to a future ‘seen
dimly,’ if at all. That is indeed why our Constitution is written as it is. The
Framers (both in 1788 and 1868) understood that the world changes. So they did
not define rights by reference to the specific practices existing at the time.
Instead, the Framers defined rights in general terms, to permit future
evolution in their scope and meaning.”) (citing NLRB v. Noel Canning, 573 U. S.
513, 533–534 (2014); McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheat. 316, 415 (1819)); id. at
*152, 177–202 and Appendix at *208–13(slip dissenting op. at 5, 30–55 and App.
at 61–66) (decrying the majority’s decision to abandon the doctrine of stare
decisis as a central rule-of-law principle that the Court is also charged to
uphold—without “special justification—to ensure the integrity, legitimacy, and
continuity of the judiciary and law). [8] See
below, note 14. [9] See
Dobbs, 597 U.S. __, at *154–163 (slip dissenting op., at 6–16) (Breyer,
Sotomayor, and Kagan, JJ., dissenting) (“We believe in a Constitution that puts
some issues off limits to majority rule. Even in the face of public opposition,
we uphold the right of individuals—yes, including women—to make their own
choices and chart their own futures. Or at least, we did once.”). [10] See
Dobbs, 597 U.S. __, at *13 (slip op. at 5) “In defending [Mississippi’s partial
ban on abortion, the State’s primary argument is that we should reconsider and
overrule Roe and Casey and once again allow each State to
regulate abortion as its citizens wish. On the other side, respondents and the
Solicitor General ask us to reaffirm Roe and Casey, and they contend that the
Mississippi law cannot stand if we do so. Allowing Mississippi to prohibit
abortions after 15 weeks of pregnancy, they argue, ‘would be no different than
overruling Casey and Roe entirely.’ They contend that “no half-measures” are
available and that we must either reaffirm or overrule Roe and Casey. We hold
that Roe and Casey must be overruled.”) (citing Brief for
Respondents 50.). [11] In
so saying, I acknowledge but take a different approach to Sandy Levinson’s
collection of essays on diversity, which examine American religion and
affirmative action cases head-on. Sanford
V. Levinson, Wrestling with Diversity (2003). [12] For
histories of abortion debates and the diversity of responses to Roe,
anchored in American conservative religious and political movements in debates
about a right to life against liberal privacy rights, see the series of books
on the issue by Mary Ziegler: Dollars for
Life: The Anti-Abortion Movement and the Fall of the Republican Establishment
(2022), Abortion and the Law in America: A Legal History, Roe v. Wade to the
Present (2020), and Beyond
Abortion: Roe v. Wade and the Battle for Privacy (2018), and After Roe: The Lost History of the Abortion
Debate (2015). For a corroborating 2021 predictive note by leading
conservative political theorist Professor Robert George that the Court’s
failure to overrule Roe and Casey would shatter the conservative
establishment, see his Roe
Will Go, First Things (Oct. 2021) (and his earlier Roe
Must Go, First Things
(Jul. 1, 2021), laying out
moral-religious and constitutional reasons why). [13] See Resource
Roundup: Abortion and Islamic Law,
Islamic Law Blog (May 24,
2022, updated Jun. 24, 2022). For mainstream positions in
classical Sunnī Islamic law, see, e.g., Ijhāḍ [Abortion], Mawsūʿa fiqhiyya [Encyclopedia of Islamic Law]
(Kuwait 1998), 2:56ff (collecting mainstream Sunnī legal sources); Muḥammad
Ḥasan al-Nujaymī, Ijhāḍ: Aḥkāmuh wa-ḥudūduh
fī al-sharīʿa al-Islāmiya waʾl-qānūn al-waḍʿī [Abortion: Related Islamic
Rulings and Limitations in Islamic Law and in Modern Law] (2016). For
Shīʿī law, see Ayatollah Sistani, Istiftāʾāt:
Isqāṭ al-Janīn [Abortion or Miscarriage], at Sistani.org (stating a leading Shīʿī positions in
response to varied questions on circumstances surrounding abortion); Ijhāḍ [Abortion],
at Wikifeqh (collecting
opinions and sources). [14] The
Court acknowledged and dismissed overtly religious views from its initial
analysis, see Dobbs, 597 U.S. __, at *9 (slip op. at 1) (“Some believe
fervently that a human person comes into being at conception and that abortion
ends an innocent life. Others feel just as strongly that any regulation of
abortion invades a woman’s right to control her own body and prevents women
from achieving full equality. Still others in a third group think that abortion
should be allowed under some but not all circumstances ….”), before discussing
its relevance historically, id., at 37–39 (slip. op. at 29–31) (discussing the
sincerely held belief and unquestioned good faith of nineteenth-century
legislators and modern abortion opponents that abortion ends human life). Cf.
id., at *134 (slip concurring op. at 11) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring). See also
id. at *154 (slip dissenting op. at 7). The varied opinions reference religious
training and values, but never mention “religion” itself. [15] See
Intisar A. Rabb, Metacanons: Comparative Textualism [forthcoming]. [16] Karl N. Llewellyn, Remarks
on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How Statutes
Are to Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev 396–406 (1950). [17] For
examples and discussion, see, e.g., Anita S. Krishnakumar, Cracking the
Whole Code Rule, 96 N.Y.U. L. Rev.
76-172 (2021), Nina A. Mendelson, Change, Creation, and Unpredictability in
Statutory Interpretation: Interpretive Canon Use in the Roberts Court's First
Decade, 117 Mich. L. Rev. 71
(2018), at https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol117/iss1/3. See also, e.g., Las Americas Immigrant Advoc. Ctr. v. Wolf, 507 F. Supp.
3d 1, 28–29 (D.D.C. 2020) (per Brown Jackson, J.). [18]
Elena Kagan, The Scalia Lecture: A Dialogue with Justice Kagan on the
Reading of Statutes, Harv. L. Today (Nov. 17, 2015), at
http://today.law.harvard.edu/in-scalia-lecture-kagan-discusses
-statutory-interpretation. Cf. William
Eskridge, Interpreting Law 81 (2016) (“We are all textualists.”). But
see West
Virginia v. Environmental Protection Agency, 597 U.S. __ (2022) (slip dissenting op. at 28) (Kagan, J., dissenting)
(“It seems I was wrong. The current Court is textualist only when being so
suits it. When that method would frustrate broader goals, special canons like
the ‘major questions doctrine’ magically appear as get out-of-text-free
cards.”). [19]
Antonin Scalia & Bryan Garner, Reading Law 69 (2012). [20]
William N. Eskridge, Jr., Interpreting Law: A Primer on how to Read Statutes
and the Constitution, 33 (2016). [21] 590 U.S. __ (2020). [22] 524
U.S. 125 (1998). The federal statute is 18 U.S.C § 924(c)(1). [23]
Muscarello, 524 U.S. at 128–39, esp. at 128. [24] Id.
at 139–40, 146 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). [25] Id.
at 145–46. [26] For
the constitutional grounding of the rule of lenity, see Intisar A. Rabb, The
Appellate Rule of Lenity
[Responding to Abbe R. Gluck & Richard A. Posner, Statutory
Interpretation on the Bench: A Survey of Forty-Two Judges on the Federal Courts
of Appeals], 131 Harv. L. Rev. F.
179 (2018). For originalist/historical arguments for expanding its use, see
Shon Hopwood, Restoring
the Historical Rule of Lenity as a Canon, 95 NYU L. Rev. 918 (2020). [27] An
example is the Qurʾānic requirement for men to wash themselves with a ritual
ablution before prayer if they have "touched" women. Qurʾān 4:43,
5:6. Most jurists applied the ordinary meaning canon contextually, to conclude
that the remedy and the then-known euphemism "touching women" means
having sex. A minority applied the ordinary meaning canon to require ritual
ablution for any kind of touch. And a third group of jurists applied the
ordinary meaning canon to adopt a third view—that the link between the named
act and the requirement of ablution indicates that the textual requirement
referred to only a special kind of touch, one done with sexual intention. See
Ibn Qudāma (d. 1223), al-Mughnī (Cairo, 1997), 1:256-60 (Yajib al-wuḍūʾ ʿalā man qabbala biʾl-shahwa wa-lā yajib
ʿalā man qabbala lil-raḥma. [Wa-]riwāya thāniya: lā yanquḍ al-lams bi-ḥāl …
illā an yaṭṭa’ahā … li-anna al-wujūb min al-sharʿ wa-lam yurid bi-hādhā sharʿ,
wa-lā huwa fī maʿnā mā warada al-sharʿ bih. Wa-qawlu <<aw lāmastum
al-nisāʾ>> maʿnāh arāda bih al-jimāʿ. Wa-riwāya thālitha: anna al-lams
yunqaḍ bi-kull ḥāl, wa-ḥaqīqat al-lams mulāqāt al-basharatayn. Qāla al-shāʿir
[Bashshār b. Burd] <<lamastu bi-kaffī kaffah aṭlab al-ghinā>>).
This example is taken from Hossein Modarressi. [28] On
the question of the moral-formal dilemma, one might add these twin principles
are an emphatic nod to two ideas that we often see, in American law, as at odds
with one another: (1) the authoritativeness of formalism and (2) the
uncertainty of morality. The Islamic law principle is a nod to the
authoritativeness of formalism because it validates the authoritativeness of
any interpretation by a judge who has gone through the formal interpretive
process—considering the text, the context, any related canons of construction,
any relevant norms from related laws or precedents, and any overarching norms
from foundational (‘constitutional’) texts. So far, this sounds a lot like the
process of an American textualist judge. The Islamic law principle is also a
nod to the uncertainty of morality because it accommodates multiple outcomes.
The consequence of recognizing a procedurally valid, or—we can say—properly
textualist, interpretation by one judge is recognition of a different
interpretation by another judge who has similarly observed the proper
textualist approach to interpretation. [29]
Sherman Jackson, The Constitutional
Jurisprudence of Shihāb al-Dīn al-Qarāfī (1996). [30] For discussion, see my Islamic Legal
Minimalism: Legal Maxims and Lawmaking When Jurists Disappear, in Law and Tradition in Classical Islamic Thought
145–66 (Najam Haider et al. eds, Palgrave Macmillan, 2013). [31]
Relatedly, were there space here to elaborate on as much, I would at more
length suggest that it is the failure to recognize that choice that leads to a formal-moral
dilemma in statutory interpretation, to use Robert Cover’s term for the
stark dissonance in constitutional interpretation (as when the Supreme Court
was asked to recognize the formal validity of Fugitive Slave laws in the
immoral system of slavery). See Robert
Cover, Justice Accused: Antislavery and the Judicial Process (Yale
1975). Cf. Sanford Levinson & Mark Graber, Justice Accused at 45:
Reflections on Robert Cover’s Masterwork, 37 Touro L. Rev. 1851–1912 (2022).
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |