E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Thus far I’ve been emphasizing one intellectual move common
to comparative inquiry: drawing nonobvious connections between superficially
disparate phenomena. That’s what both Sandy
and Mark are doing. The sibling move is to
unearth underappreciated distinctions between superficially similar
phenomena. That’s what Yuval is up to in
his fascinating discussion of safeties and touchdowns.
The asymmetry that Yuval identifies is this: when the
offense commits a penalty in its own end zone, the infraction constitutes a
safety and results in the award of (two) points to the defense, but when the
defense commits a penalty in its end zone, the offense is not awarded a
touchdown and its (six) points, but instead keeps possession of the ball at the
one-yard line. To make sense of this
apparent inconsistency, Yuval proposes that safeties and touchdowns are
conceptually distinct phenomena: touchdowns must be caused, whereas safeties
simply are.
Maybe. There’s a lot
packed into his argument. And while
there is much I am tempted to say in response, for the sake of brevity (too
late!) I’ll just toss out a competing account that I am disposed to favor. I’d say that it’s the rule that defines and
thus constitutes safeties that actually embraces two conceptually distinct
kinds of things. The first kind of
safety is a scoring play that the defense executes by tackling the ball carrier
in its own end zone. The second kind is
a penalty on the offense for committing an infraction in its end zone where the
usual form of penalty—loss of yards—is (thought) unavailable. Scoring safeties are like touchdowns; penalty
safeties are not. On my way of carving
things, but not Yuval’s, it would be truer to the underlying logic if the 2
points that attach to a safety were subtracted from the offense’s score in the
case of penalty safeties and added to the defense’s score only in the case of
scoring safeties. Although the
competitive consequence is the same either way, truth in advertising might
favor this change in much the same way that the NFL already distinguishes
between “stands” and “confirmed” as two functionally equivalent verdicts after
instant replay review. To summarize, and
taking a page from a classic
article, we might ask: How many kinds of safety does NFL Rule 11
constitute? (a) 1; (b) 2; (c) 3; (d)
more. Yuval, I think, says (a). I’ve thus far suggested (b).
But matters might be more complicated still. Consider a third situation that results in a
safety: when, after an impetus by the offense, the ball travels out of bounds
beyond the goal line. We know how Yuval
classifies this, for all types of safety are, for him, fundamentally the same
sort of thing. But what about for
me? Is this an instance of a scoring
safety or a penalty safety? Or does it
represent a conceptually distinguishable third type of safety? Is it a constitutive rule, neither a scoring
rule nor a penalty rule? Or is it a prophylactic
rule that backs up one of the other types of safety and, if so, would it pass
congruence and proportionality? Either
way, the answer to my question might be (c).
While each of the contributions is excellent, I probably
learned most from Jodi’s because the perspective she offers—“an insider’s view”
on the making, amending, and enforcing of rules in the NFL—is most foreign to
my own experience. Beyond thanking her
for educating me, I’ll limit myself to one quibble and one more substantive observation.
My quibble concerns Jodi’s suggestion that the New Orleans
Saints lobbied for instant replay review of pass interference calls (and
non-calls) to achieve “post-season vindication” and without “any particular
theory of the game” to back it up. Given
that one lesson her contribution teaches is that the NFL aims to realize a multiplicity
of ends—a lesson that vindicates my own thoroughly pluralist sensibilities—I’m a
little unsure what she means by “theory of the game.” The current NFL replay
system dates to 1999, when it was introduced, as one senior official explained
(discussed here),
precisely because the League didn’t “want anyone not going to the Super Bowl
because of an error that could be corrected.”
Even if they were operating without a fully blown “theory of the game,”
surely the Saints had a perfectly good League-certified principle to rely on:
that consequential final calls should be correct if possible. Instant replay of pass interference failed,
in my judgment, not because it’s too ad hoc or unprincipled but because it’s
hard to operationalize in a manner that significantly improves accuracy without
substantial additional delay—which is why asking students to try to fix the
problem is a great group exercise.
My final observation.
Jodi concludes by identifying lessons that rulemakers in law
(legislators and regulators) might draw from the NFL’s rulemaking process. All she says here strikes me as right and
interesting. I’d add a lesson for interpreters
and legal theorists. Positivists believe that the legally proper approach to textual
interpretation in any given legal system is somehow determined by or grounded
in certain practices of certain groups of people. Those practices evolve in response to pressures
and incentives from the interpretive environment. One highly relevant feature of the
environment concerns the rapidity and reliability of formal rule revision. As Jodi explains, formal rule revision in the
NFL is highly rapid and reliable. One
should expect textualism to be stricter in NFL football than in U.S. statutory
law, where it is in turn stricter than in U.S. constitutional law.
As these comments are now overlong, as well as
overdue, this is a good place to stop.
I’ll return to the beginning by reiterating my gratitude to the
symposiasts for their keen and kind commentaries on our book, and to our host
for making it possible.
Mitchell Berman is the Leon Meltzer Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy at the University of Pennsylvania. You can reach him by e-mail at mitchber@law.upenn.edu.