Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Reasons to Doubt Whether “the Best Way Forward Is To Look Backward”: Commentary on Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism
|
Tuesday, July 12, 2022
Reasons to Doubt Whether “the Best Way Forward Is To Look Backward”: Commentary on Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism (Polity Press 2022). Linda
C. McClain
In
Common Good Constitutionalism,
Professor Adrian Vermeule asserts that breaking with the last few generations
of constitutional interpretation by looking “backward for inspiration” to
“classical law” is the “best way forward” to “restore the integrity of our law
and of our legal traditions.” Vermeule bluntly contends that “our public law”
oscillates fruitlessly between two interpretive “camps,” originalism and
progressivism. He would replace this “exhausted opposition” with a third
approach, “common good constitutionalism.” That approach would recover and
adapt “the world of the classical tradition” as “the matrix within which
American judges read our Constitution, our statutes, and our administrative
law.” This classical legal tradition, Vermuele contends, predated “the founding
area” and remained “central” to the American legal world until the mid-20th
century. Vermeule describes this tradition variously, for example: (1) the “ius commune”—“the classical European
synthesis of Roman law, canon law, and local civil law;” (2) the “ordinary
cosmology” of “divine law, natural law, and civil or ‘municipal’ law;” (3) a blend
of natural law and natural rights; and (4) a mix of civil law, natural law, and
the law of nations. But whatever the description of the classical tradition to
which Vermeule would look backward, there are good reasons to resist this
disruptive move. For
disruption is, indeed, what Vermeule seeks. Using Ronald Dworkin’s famous image
of legal interpretation as writing a long “chain novel,” Vermeule calls for “ripping
up substantial segments” of that novel—sometimes reinterpreting certain
“chapters” in “drastic terms.” Vermeule does not spell out the full scope of
the disruption, but the examples that he does give concerning constitutional
liberty and equality are troubling, as is his rhetoric. Further, Vermeule says little
about how a revived and adapted classical tradition would address problems of
gender and racial inequality recognized by current Supreme Court jurisprudence
as incompatible with the Fourteenth Amendment. Again, what we do learn is
troubling. In
this post, I will begin with a few points on which I agree with Vermeule: the
necessity for a “moral reading” of the U.S. Constitution and for a positive constitutionalism, rather than an
originalist reading and a view of the Constitution as simply a charter of
negative liberties. I will then raise several concerns about Vermeule’s
disruptive project, illustrating with (1) the historical role of appeals to
natural law and divine law in justifying sex and race inequality, including in family
law, the institution of marriage, and in civil society; (2) Vermeule’s
caricatured depiction of what he calls “progressive constitutionalism,” and his
emphatic rejection of autonomy as a basis for Due Process liberty; and (3) the
seeming absence of the role of deliberation by the people and of appreciation
of reasonable moral pluralism in his conception of common good
constitutionalism. First,
a few points of agreement: I agree with Vermeule that originalism is an “illusion”
because it fails to recognize that constitutional interpretation requires
principles of political morality. Here Vermeule credits Ronald Dworkin’s call
for “moral readings of the Constitution”—even though he “emphatically” rejects
Dworkin’s liberal moral commitments and liberal account of rights. Further, I
also agree with Vermeule’s characterization of “living originalists” as being moral
readers. Here Vermeule echoes (although without citing)
James Fleming’s earlier argument, in Fidelity to
Our Imperfect Constitution: For Moral Readings and Against Originalisms, that once originalists—including proponents of “living originalism” such as Jack Balkin—recognize that the Constitution includes broad
and abstract moral terms (such as “liberty” and “equality”) whose meaning
embodies broad, abstract principles of political morality, and not just “concrete
historical practices,” they have left originalism behind. I
also agree with Vermeule’s project of “common good constitutionalism” to the
extent that it recognizes the need for a positive
constitutionalism and appeals to the positive aims for establishing a
government set out in the Preamble. As Sot Barber, Stephen Macedo, and Jim
Fleming argue,
“positive constitutionalism is neither new nor inconsistent with American
traditions” and properly moves from thinking not only about “negative
liberties” but also about positive ends. It views government as dedicated
chiefly for public purposes. In Ordered
Liberty, ] Jim Fleming and I
embraced this view, arguing—against the then-recent Supreme Court—that the Constitution
is “a charter of positive benefits: as instrument for pursuing good things like
the ends proclaimed in the Preamble, for which We the People ordained and
established the Constitution.” Of
course, there is no single account of how to interpret those ends or “the
common good”—and here Vermeule and I part company. Fleming and I argued for a
constitutional liberalism that included, among other things, a “formative
project” of cultivating civic virtues and capacities necessary to secure
ordered liberty. Both in Common Good Constitutionalism
and in other writings, Vermeule is a sharp critic of liberalism and would
likely characterize Fleming and my approach as a species of problematic
“progressive constitutionalism” (more on that below). Vermeule instead offers a
“moral reading” that looks to the classical tradition to flesh out the common
good. I now turn to why this is a disruptive, even subversive
project. First,
consider again what’s in the “stew” of the classical legal tradition that
Vermeule would revive and adapt. Divine law, natural law, and civil law have
all starred in justifying status hierarchy in marriage as well as the exclusion
of women—married or unmarried—from full participation in civic, political, and
economic life. Vermeule quotes Blackstone on the “cosmology” of classical law.
Blackstone’s account of the disabilities to which wives were subject under the
common law model of “coverture” marriage—during which “the very being or legal
existence of the woman is suspended, or . . . incorporated and consolidated
into that of the husband”—traveled to the colonies and shaped the law of
domestic relations in the states. In 1873, in Bradwell v. Illinois, concurring Justice Bradley famously appealed
to “the constitution of the family organization, which is founded in the divine
ordinance” as well as to “the nature of things” to rationalize the “domestic
sphere” as that “which properly belong to the domain and functions of
womanhood” and “unfits” women for “many of the occupations of civil life.” The
gender revolution in the Court’s interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause
in the 1970s and 1980s contributed to the dismantling of coverture marriage, a
process that began through feminist advocacy and state law reform even in the
19th century. In cases such as Planned
Parenthood v. Casey and Obergefell v.
Hodges, the Supreme Court has looked back to Justice Bradley’s concurrence
to chart the gulf between those earlier conceptions of the family, marriage,
women’s role, and the Constitution itself and present-day understandings. When
Vermeule speaks of ripping up recent chapters in the chain novel, he does not
tell us of the fate of the transformation of family law and the law of marriage
away from status hierarchy. By what criteria will revivers of the classical
tradition separate what they carry forward as distinguished from what they
leave behind? Presumably, Vermeule does not seek to revive coverture marriage, with
a wife’s suspension of identity, loss of property rights, duty to obey and
serve her husband, or the husband’s right to physically “chastise” his wife and
his immunity from rape. But how will common good constitutionalists decide how
to adapt the classical tradition? How
should classical law inform constitutional law and marriage and family? If we
are to look to Roman law, for example, surely we cannot take on board Roman
society’s status hierarchy of free citizens versus slaves, or some of its
practices, like “concubinage.” Family law and religion scholar John Witte, Jr.
has detailed the “creative convergence” of classical and early Christian ideas and traditions
about marriage and family with “modern liberties” concerning sex, marriage, and
family life. It took Enlightenment thinkers such as Mary Wollstonecraft and
Frances Hutcheson, Witte concludes, to help push the Western legal tradition to
“remove the many layers of patriarchy and coverture” and, eventually, to more
fully realize in law itself ideals of sex equality in marriage and in the
broader society. Vermeule
does not tell us a similar tale of shedding status hierarchies, although he
tells readers that constitutional law should elaborate “subsidiary principles”
that include respect for “the hierarchies needed for society to function.” He
elaborates that “common good constitutionalism does not suffer from a horror of
legitimate hierarchy, because it sees that law can encourage those subject to
the law to form desires, habits, and beliefs that better track and promote
communal well-being.” Of course, we need to know: what is “legitimate”
hierarchy? Vermeule mentions status hierarchies when he critiques—or, in my
view—caricatures progressive constitutionalism. He claims that progressive
constitutionalism has an “overarching sacramental narrative” of “the relentless
expansion of individualistic autonomy.” It insists on liberation from an
endless set of hierarchies and constraints. But were none of those hierarchies
properly challenged as unduly limiting human freedom? Vermeule does not tell
us. To
return to the example of marriage: Vermeule suggests that progressives seek
liberation from, among other things, family, but never addresses whether the
classical law’s model of marriage included gender-based status hierarchy that
constitutional law properly played a role in dismantling with evolving
understanding of the status of women under the Constitution and in society. Vermeule
clearly believes that one legitimate family hierarchy would be limiting the
definition of marriage to one man and one woman. Enlisting natural law and the
writings of the 6th century Byzantine emperor Justinian, he critiques
Obergefell’s extension of the
fundamental right to marry to same-sex couples. Vermeule argues that common
good constitutionalism would recognize that marriage is “a natural and moral
and legal reality simultaneously.” Marriage is “a form . . . constituted by the
natural law in general terms as the permanent union of man and woman under the
general telos or indwelling aims of
unity and procreation (whether or not the particular couple is contingently capable
of procreating).” On that view, “for the civil authority to specify in law that
marriage can only be the union or a man and a woman fits the telos of the
institution and thus determines through the civil law what the natural law
prescribes in any event.” Obergefell,
thus, “warped the core nature” of marriage by “forcibly removing one of its
built-in structural features,” namely, reproduction. Instead, Vermeule praises
Justice Alito’s dissent for observing that, “for millennia, marriage was inextricably
linked to the one thing that only an opposite-sex couples can do: procreate.”
Vermeule also embraces the Obergefell
dissenters’ unjustified charges of “bigotry” with respect to the reasoning of
Justice Kennedy’s majority opinion about why excluding same-sex couples from
civil marriage violated their liberty and equality. While
Vermeule invokes Justinian’s writings on marriage, this teleological argument closely
parallels arguments about marriage asserted (unsuccessfully) in constitutional
litigation by conservative political theorist Robert George and coauthors
Sherif Girgis and Ryan Anderson. I have challenged that argument against civil
marriage equality elsewhere as
inconsistent with contemporary family law and constitutional law, and will not
repeat those argument here. But a question arises: what else will modern
interpreters of the U.S. Constitution take on board when they look to natural
law, Justinian, and other classical accounts of marriage? Defenses of criminal
laws barring interracial marriage frequently appealed to divine law, natural
hierarchy, and natural law. Further, as I elaborated in Who’s the
Bigot?, the “theology
of segregation” and the “theology of integration” offered starkly contrasting
appeals to divine law as well as to how “founding” principles should shape
constitutional interpretation and civil rights laws. Vermeule’s book is notably
silent about problems like religiously-inspired racism and white supremacy. Finally,
Vermeule does not offer a persuasive reason why personal autonomy in making
significant decisions is not a more persuasive reading of the “liberty’
protected under the Due Process Clause that his non-liberal classical
conception. On his conception, “rights, properly understood, are always ordered
to the common good and that common good is itself the highest individual
interest.” But there is no unitary understanding of the common good. It is not clear
that Vermeule’s trio of “justice, peace, and abundance” maps well onto the
practice of constitutional law, or, in any case, exhausts the common good. Vermeule
promises that “common good constitutionalism” will render vulnerable the
Court’s jurisprudence on “abortion, sexual liberties, and related matters.”
Vermeule wrote these words before Justice Alito’s majority opinion in Dobbs overruled Roe and Casey, using the
narrow approach to liberty taken in Washington
v. Glucksberg and putting in question the entire “fabric” of constitutional
liberty. Dobbs itself portends disruption
of constitutional practice, or tearing up chapters of the chain novel. Vermeule
presumably supports the ruling in Dobbs,
even if he might have adopted a different method of justification, given his
critique of originalism. For example, Vermeule calls the Casey joint opinion “notorious.” In dramatic rhetoric, he argues
that Casey’s language about the right
to “define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe and of
the mystery of human life” should be “not only rejected but stamped as abominable, beyond the realm
of the acceptable forever after.” (Emphasis added). Vermeule’s non-recognition
and non-response to the well-developed arguments justifying Casey and other substantive due process
cases is emblematic of his abandonment of public reason, reasoned judgment in
constitutional interpretation, and pluralism. In a
footnote, Vermeule shares his view that the best reading of due process, equal
protection, along with “other constitutional provisions” would “grant unborn
children a positive or affirmative right to life that states must respect in
their criminal and civil law.” Such a view is not a “mere rejection” of Roe; it affirms this “opposite right,”
which “would be binding throughout the nation.” Finally,
and remarkably, given his claim to be developing a common good
constitutionalism, Vermeule gives no indication that he understands that the
common good is a generic concept that is common to many political and constitutional
theories, not a concept that is peculiar to what he calls the classical
tradition. For example, conceptions of civic republicanism, civic liberalism,
and deliberative democracy are all theories of common good constitutionalism. Sot
Barber has given the literature’s most thorough argument for a common good constitutionalism and positive
constitutionalism. Furthermore, unlike other theories of common good
constitutionalism, Vermeule does not seem to contemplate deliberation by the
people as public-spirited citizens concerning what constitutes the common good.
Instead, he seems to contemplate that rulers will reason about the classical
tradition and ascertain what is good for the people. I
close by expressing my profound doubt that a free and equal
people—characterized by reasonable moral pluralism—would submit to such rule. Linda C. McClain is Robert Kent Professor of Law, Boston University School of Law. You can reach her by e-mail at lmcclain@bu.edu.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |