Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts "Power to the People" -- Response to the Review Symposium
|
Monday, March 14, 2022
"Power to the People" -- Response to the Review Symposium
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric We
thank all the contributors to the review-symposium for their thoughtful
engagement with Power to the People. Responding in detail to all the
observations – both supportive and critical – would exceed readers’ patience,
so we confine ourselves to some matters where, we think, we can contribute to a
productive conversation about the book’s arguments. Several comments point to what we
regard as fruitful lines of inquiry to pursue within the general
framework we develop; others are challenges to some of our basic assumptions.
Professor Graber raises two questions that we regard as intertwined, for
example. He picks up on our passing acknowledgement of Robert Michels’s iron
law of oligarchy and suggests (in our reading) that future research on populist
parties and movements might identify the characteristics of the elites who,
Michels argues, inevitably come to dominate such parties and movements. We
agree that some systematic inquiry along those lines might be quite
enlightening. We
think such an inquiry might connect to a second question Professor Graber
raises: Under what conditions do what he calls the more inclusive or pluralist
strands of populism degenerate into exclusive and antipluralist versions. Professor
Ó’Cinnéide echoes this concern in his argument that we underestimate the extent
to which some forms of populism can be democratic irritants, the response to
which might be a rejection of some elements of democracy. These are interesting
empirical questions – and we note that they can be posed only if scholars
accept our argument (and others’, of course) that populism isn’t by definition
antipluralist or antidemocratic in tendency. Moreover, our own reading of the
political science literature is that that question rather depends on other
structural features exogenous to populism (host ideology, the leader’s character,
and others). Professor
Suteu also brings some empirical questions to the fore. Acknowledging that
populist political parties and leaders choose among instruments for determining
what (in their view) the people prefer, she asks about the conditions under
which they choose one or another instrument. So, for example, what are the
political conditions that lead populist parties to put questions to a
referendum or to ordinary lawmaking by bodies in which they have a majority? We
have no well-informed views about those questions. We note, though, one matter
worth exploring. Sometimes a referendum might be preferred because public
engagement in the campaign will build support for the party (the
referendum in Hungary to be held this year on restricting LGBTQ rights, for
example); sometimes it might build more enduring support for the policy
(in our admittedly controversial view, the Irish referendum on marriage
equality). Like
Professor Ó’Cinnéide’s Professor Dixon’s comments pivot between asking
empirical questions within our general approach and questions about that
approach. As to the former, for example, she notes that we don’t distinguish
clearly between populist movements and populist political parties, and in
particular observes that leadership characteristics might differ in the two
forms. We agree that this is an important and under-researched question: At the
anecdotal level differences between Viktor Orbán, leading a (perhaps) populist
political party, and Evo Morales, which began as a leader of a populist
movement that transformed into a populist party, seem worth thinking about. Professor
Dixon also raises a more general concern. She worries that our insistence on
distinguishing among populisms, coupled with our thin definition of
constitutionalism, might be ill-suited for those who, as she puts it, are
interested in devising ex ante constitutional controls designed to reduce the
risk that problematic forms of populism will come into power. To a large extent
we agree with her. Our disagreement is perhaps about a deeper question, which
put a bit snidely is that the very purpose of ex ante constitutional designs is
to remove issues from ordinary political contention. They reflect a fear of
politics as such within, as Professor Dixon of course acknowledges, some
restricted domains. The tricky questions are these: (1) Can we identify ex ante
the boundary between the domain in which ordinary politics governs and the ones
removed from such contention in a way that reduces the risk of “bad” populism
without too severely constricting the range of permissible political choices?
Our position, expressed through our thin definition of constitutionalism, is
that doing so is extremely difficult, perhaps even impossible. And (2) even if
the boundary is drawn, will it be stable or, more precisely, for how long is it
likely to be stable? One important
theorization used slavery in the ante bellum United States and abortion in the
contemporary United States as examples of issues whose constitutionalization
supposedly took the issues off the table, which suggests the empirical
difficulty of this question. And, beyond empirical difficulty, there’s the political-theory
one, suggested by Professor Bellamy’s invocation of political
constitutionalism, that taking anything out of the domain of ordinary
political contestation is problematic in reasonably well-functioning
democracies. We
turn now to the more fundamental challenges to some of our arguments some of
the responses offer. Our book begins with chapters defining constitutionalism
and populism. Professors Bellamy, Wilkinson, and Khaitan argue that our
definitions are defective. Our response begins by stating two presuppositions
about definitions that shaped our initial presentation: They should be useful
for the purposes to which they are put and they should be no more precise than
are the objects they seek to identify. So,
for example, Professors Loughlin and Wilkinson criticize our use of a thin
definition of constitutionalism because it doesn’t capture the “historical and
material” (Wilkinson) realities of the form of constitutionalism expressed
widely in contemporary Europe and the United States. That form of
constitutionalism is “a specific philosophy of governing” that began as a means
to “institute a regime of limited government” and works today to support
“policies that embrace globalization and open statehood” (Loughlin). We have no
deep quarrels with that definition when used for its own purposes, as a
critique of what Professor Loughlin (supported to some degree by Professor
Wilkinson) describe as the contemporary constitutional situation in Europe and
the United States. We
wonder, though, why they think that their definition is useful in addressing
the questions we are interested in, and in particular the claim, widely
prevalent in the literature on populism and constitutionalism, that populism is
inconsistent with constitutionalism. Maybe they believe that the literature has
taken a wrong turn and that addressing its concerns is a waste of time. Some of
what they write, though, suggests that they too think that dealing with the
relation between populism and their thicker versions of constitutionalism is
worthwhile. At one point, for example, Professor Wilkinson seems to argue that
Italian populism is actually compatible with the thicker constitutionalism he describes.
And there are more than hints in their responses of the common claim that
populism is a reaction to that thicker constitutionalism, as people left behind
by globalization and open statehood reject the policies forced upon them by
governing elites in the name of constitutionalism. Professor Bellamy expands on
the claim though he doesn’t endorse it fully. We’re
sympathetic to that claim, adverted to briefly in our book. We refrained from getting
behind it, though. Professor Bellamy explains our concerns. The claim is
contentious among political scientists who disagree about the relative
explanatory power of “socio-cultural” or “economic-political backlash.” For
example, survey evidence from the United States suggests, though not conclusively,
that Donald Trump’s core supporters aren’t in fact people who work in sectors
distinctively disadvantaged by globalization and the like. And evaluating the
causal arguments is outside our wheelhouse. So, in sum, the thicker definitions
of constitutionalism that Professors Loughlin and Wilkinson prefer are suitable
for their purposes, less suitable for ours. Professor
Wilkinson also criticizes us for saying a lot about what populism isn’t and not
so much about what populism is. That does indeed accurately describe our
presentation, though we think it a strength rather than a weakness. The reason
is that far too often scholars and political commentators use “populism” as
what philosopher C.L. Stevenson would call a “boo!” word. In the literature on
populism to which we refer the term “populism” is attached, sometimes with an
accompanying adjective, to political parties and leaders who win elections, or
come close to winning them, on unworthy policy platforms. In some ways our core
argument about populism is that this is a conceptual mistake however
effective it might as a form of political rhetoric. So, for example, Professor
Wilkinson refers to works describing Margaret Thatcher as an authoritarian
populist and cites a scholar who calls Angela Merkel a technopopulist. It seems
to us that the adjectives are doing all the work here, and that calling these
politicians “populists” leaches that term of any analytic value except as an
indication of the fact that they won elections rather than forced their
policies down the throats of disfranchised citizens. We
think more valuable Professor Ó’Cinnéide’s observation that “populist tropes
lurk[] in every corner of the political spectrum,” and his reference to them as
an “antisystem electoral strategy … that is part of the technology of
democratic competition.” For us, the critical enterprise of treating many
features said to characterize populism as features of ordinary political life
is more useful – again, for our purposes if not for others’ – than attempting
to distill what is essential to populism as such. Professor
Bellamy’s milder objection to our thin definition of constitutionalism operates
a bit differently. He treats our thin constitutionalism as a regulative ideal:
If the requirements of thin constitutionalism are satisfied the normative goals
said to be promoted by constitutionalism, such as creating a framework for
determining and then advancing the public good, will be achieved. But, he
argues, thin constitutionalism might not do so and therefore can’t be a
regulative ideal. We agree with that proposition because we didn’t offer thin
constitutionalism as a regulative ideal. For us, as other commenters indicate,
it's something like a common core to thicker versions of constitutionalism such
as that offered by Professor Khaitan. Taken as a regulative ideal, thin
constitutionalism might conduce to limited government of a neoliberal sort,
though we think that establishing that proposition would take quite a bit of
empirical and theoretical work. Our
discussion of the possibility of “good” populisms expresses our view that thin
constitutionalism can lead, as Professor Bellamy puts it, to “more government.”
On the face of it, the very thinness of our version – the fact that it doesn’t
take much off the table of ordinary political contestation – would seem to
enable a wide range of policy choices. Perhaps we’re wrong because, at least in
a world where power (including political power) is distributed in the
normatively troubling way described by Professors Wilkinson and Loughlin, you need
a thicker constitution to get more government. That’s partly an empirical
question and partly a call for political mobilization against the current
distribution of power. We’re not specialists in political activism, of course.
What we offer in the book’s concluding part are some suggestions about
institutional reforms that activists might consider taking up. Like
Professor Bellamy, Professor Khatain sees us as prescribing thin
constitutionalism as a normative ideal. His position, though, is stronger than
Professor Bellamy’s because for him we present thin constitutionalism as “the
exclusive normative standard in relation to a state’s institutional setup.” As
our discussion already indicates, we think that’s a straight-forward misreading
of what we have to say. Though we’re quite tentative in saying the following,
we suspect that Professor Khaitan’s mistake results from his desire for more
definitional precision than is appropriate when we’re dealing with
constitutionalism. This comes out, for us, in his insistence that there’s
something truly important about distinguishing between using “constitutional”
and using “constitutionalist.” Maybe for some purposes drawing that distinction
is important, but not, we think, for studying the actual operation of real
institutions in the messy world of politics (by which we mean the discussion
and choice of policy outcomes where people disagree about what’s best for them
and their society). In
passing we note that including some degree of entrenchment a criterion for thin
constitutionalism doesn’t exclude the United Kingdom because there are several
mechanisms for ensuring that some arrangements or rights aren’t subject to
displacement by ordinary legislative majorities. The most prominent of course is
review by courts of legislation challenged as de-entrenching. Another is the
identification in the constitution itself of some provisions enforced as
Professor Bellamy would have it by political contestation with the effect of
obstructing de-entrenchment by ordinary, transient political majorities.
(There’s a tricky technical question here about whether we should regard “mere”
power-conferring provisions as entrenched; we forgo discussion for reasons of
space.) And, finally, there’s the UK method of entrenchment, which as Professor
Khaitan says is through political culture. Professor
Khaitan points out that including majority rule in our definition of thin
constitutionalism rules out consociational arrangements. That’s a fair point,
and we should have deal with it in the book. Our initial response is along
empirical lines. Professor Khaitan says correctly that consociationalism has
been part of the constitutional tool kit for a long time. Our sense is that it
has fallen out of favor, perhaps because it has been less successful in
ensuring social peace than its strongest proponents had hoped and perhaps
relatedly because it hasn’t proved stable enough to be a useful design tool.
But the question deserves more attention because of the possibility manifesting
itself in some nations of populist governments overriding previous formal or
informal consociational constraints on what a majority ethnic group can do. We
conclude with some observations about the commenters’ discussions of our
suggestions for empowered democracy in and after populism. The first is perhaps
obvious. Despite parenthetical observations by Professors Bellamy and Khaitan,
we don’t endorse (further) judicialization of constitutional values. We’re more
inclined to reinvigorating the political constitution to which Professor
Bellamy refers, and to supporting institutional innovations that, as he says,
would encourage “deliberation and contestation.” These include “devolving power
to different regions,” or what we called substantial decentralization. That’s
one response to Professor Suteu’s concern about the extent to which some of the
deliberative processes we discuss, such as citizen assemblies and deliberative
polling, can scale to national levels. There’s obvious ground for worry, but we
note several points. (1) A well-designed deliberative poll might actually be more
accurate in determining what “the public” believes to be good policy all things
considered than a legislature whose representatives are chosen in elections in
which parties present aggregate platforms. (2) Some new forms of democratic
engagement have been successfully scaled up, the most notable being
participatory budgeting in Brazil, which by all accounts has (sometimes) been
reasonably effective at the regional level. (3) Theorists such as Hélène
Landemore and Camila Vergara, whose work we mention, have developed mechanisms
that they believe would allow for successful scaling. (4) And, finally, to
return to Professor Bellamy’s observation, the issue of scaling-up arises, as
it were, only when we worry about decisions at scale. But, we suggest, some
decisions might best be taken in radically decentralized policy-making bodies,
where the issue of scale wouldn’t arise.
Again
we thank the participants in this review-symposium for their thoughtful
engagement with Power to the People. We hope that the symposium will
enhance readers’ understanding of the book (and perhaps attract more readers to
it!). Mark Tushnet is William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law emeritus at Harvard Law School. You can reach him by e-mail at mtushnet@law.harvard.edu. Bojan Bugaric is Professor of Law at the University of Sheffield. You can reach him by e-mail at b.bugaric@sheffield.ac.uk.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |