E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Deeply researched and beautifully
written, Phantoms of a Beleaguered Republic takes a close look at the
Trump presidency and reveals “a polity driven to wit’s end by two wildly
different conceptions” of what good government entails (p. 11). The Deep State
and the Unitary Executive “are both distillations of ambition and fear,
larger-than-life projections onto issues and arrangements that are all too
real” (p. 193). As the authors recognize, either phantom—an executive branch
that privileges depth or one that trains on unitary authority—could plausibly claim
a foothold in the U.S. Constitution (p. 201). But it is the Unitary Executive
that has assumed the “lawyer’s brief” (p. 9, 29), unfolding, in the hands of
lawyers and jurists, as an argument about immutable constitutional commitments
anchored in legal text and rooted in some imagined original consensus. That
legalistic rhetoric has obscured and distracted from the central normative question
that the twin phantoms pose—in the authors’ crisp articulation, “whether we
value what depth has to offer” (p. 195-198).
In this sense, Phantoms of a
Beleaguered Republic is a meditation on the perils of structural
constitutional legalism as an instrument of American state-building. Indeed,
the authors lament a “doubling down on the Constitution” that has made “[o]ur
thinking about separation and checks . . . correspondingly narrow, rigid, and
reactive” (p. 202). And they yearn for an earlier time when the Constitution
got what it deserved: “a wink and a nod” (p. 201).
What I want to suggest, however,
is that the problem is less American constitutionalism than the legalism that
today passes for it. When it comes to the design of the state, the question
need not be whether extra-constitutional measures are politically feasible. It
can be a different way to understand the Constitution itself. In exposing the pathologies
that our court-centric, formalist, and purportedly fixed Constitution has fueled,
Phantoms of a Beleaguered Republic invites, implicitly at least, a more
developmental approach to constitutional interpretation itself.
What might a developmental
approach to constitutional interpretation entail? As Stephen Skowronek has
argued in earlier
work (co-authored with Karen Orren), “the insistence on treating every
state of affairs as in transition, a state as it were, in the process of
becoming, sets [American Political Development’s] understanding of politics
apart” (The Search for American Political Development, at p. 19). This
idea of a state in the process of becoming—or what
I have elsewhere discussed as the provisionality of our constitutional
order—is at the crux of a developmental approach to constitutional interpretation
as well. In centering provisionality over fixity, a developmental approach to
constitutional interpretation suggests a different role for history, a
different goal for constitutionalism, and a different set of sources to look to
in comprising it.
A developmental approach to
interpretation rejects the premise that careful historiography of the Founding era
can uncover a clear, static meaning to the criteria for state-building
expressed in Article II. Rather, it understands the central role of history in
constitutional inquiry to be destabilizing: to illuminate the
contingency of current governing arrangements, or the ways in which executive
power has been constructed and reconstructed over time. On this understanding
of the Constitution, the role of history is not to claim a winner between unitariness
and depth (on originalist or other grounds).
Rather, it is to elucidate how depth and unitariness have been partially
reinforced, partially rejected in different configurations and in response to
different political contingencies over time.
A developmental approach thus suggests
a different goal for constitutional interpretation as well. It “imagine[s] the
Constitution,” as Louis
Michael Seidman has argued, “as a site for contestation” that reinforces,
even in our disagreements, “a common framework” (On Constitutional
Disobedience, at 138). The constitutional vocabulary of checks and balances,
of distinct and articulated government functions, of democratic accountability,
of effective and non-arbitrary governance should serve to structure our
contestations about the desirable designs of the state. Those constitutional ideals
should help us to unpack the question “whether [and why] we value what depth
has to offer.” But the goal of constitutional interpretation is not to provide
definitive answers—let alone one-size-fits-all and immutable answers—for the structure
of American constitutional government.
Finally, a developmental approach
privileges different kinds of materials in constituting our constitutional
structure. As Niko Bowie and I argue in a forthcoming article, it uplifts
different kinds of deciders. Rather than privilege judicial decrees, we argue
that constitutional meaning emerges from statutes. This is not because statutes
reveal one particular understanding of the Constitution to be right, but
precisely because they instantiate provisional understandings of the presidency
over time—as the result of representation, negotiation, and statecraft. Indeed,
as Phantoms of a Beleaguered Republic reveals, statutes have provided an
important foundation for depth—in its various guises of knowledge, staffing, appointments,
and oversight (pp. 59-193). A developmental approach to constitutional
interpretation asks not whether those statutes conform with any one (or five)
judge’s understanding of a first-best approximation of “vesting” or “executive
power” under Article II. Instead, a developmental approach would look to those
statutes as constituting durable, though not unchangeable, accounts of executive
authority and its complex institutional layers.
A developmental approach to
constitutional interpretation thus embraces the role of politics—and of the political
process—in comprising constitutional meaning. In so doing, it permits the
ideals of political equality and republican liberty (involving, as
Philip Pettit defines it, “the permanent possibility of contesting what
government decides”) to infuse our ongoing constitutional commitments. If
constitutional text, structure, and history does not offer us one “right” way
to read the Constitution—if there is reasonable disagreement all the way
down—then statutes reflect the best mechanism we have to manage the conflicting
urges of unitariness and depth: American representative democracy.
Phantoms of a Beleaguered Republic
ultimately turns to “republican remedies” to manage these dual aspirations for executive
governance. The book invaluably orients reform thinking to instruments of
collective responsibility and collaborative controls on administration. But to the
extent the book construes republican government as built on “constitutional
heresies” (p. 202), it accepts an account of the Constitution that is unworthy
of republican values. Republican remedies should not be disentangled from the
Constitution. They must reform the project of constitutional interpretation
itself.
Daphna Renan is the Peter B.
Munroe and Mary J. Munroe Professor of Law at Harvard Law School. You can reach her by e-mail at drenan at law.harvard.edu.