Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Marriage Equality and the Sex Discrimination Argument for LGBTQ+ Rights: The Legacy of Ruth Bader Ginsburg
|
Friday, January 22, 2021
Marriage Equality and the Sex Discrimination Argument for LGBTQ+ Rights: The Legacy of Ruth Bader Ginsburg
Guest Blogger
For the Balkinization symposium on William N. Eskridge, Jr., and Christopher Riano, Marriage Equality: From Outlaws to In-Laws (Yale University Press, 2020). William N. Eskridge Jr. & Christopher R. Riano We
are honored by the attention paid to our book, Marriage Equality: From
Outlaws to In-Laws (Yale Press 2020). Jack Balkin has assembled a diverse
array of learned and brilliant commentators who have approached the book from
different angles: they situate the tome
in the context of evolving American families and family law (Naomi Cahn, June
Carbone, and Doug NeJaime), the legal process and constitutional reasoning
(Stuart Delery and Andy Koppelman), critical race and feminist theory (Russell
Robinson, as well as Koppelman), and the fraught clashes between religious
liberty and equality for sexual and gender minorities (Robin Wilson). These
intellectuals treat marriage equality for LGBTQ+ persons as an admirable social
movement and Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644 (2015) as a landmark to
be celebrated—but also to be soberly assessed with regard to the social costs
and missed opportunities. If we are not
mistaken, all of these commentators agree with the central argument of the
book, that marriage equality emerged from the changing role and status of women
in American society and from the sexual revolution. Lesbians and gay men, and later bisexuals and
transgender persons, came out of their closets and gradually gained normative
traction in the country. Delery quotes
Judge Shelby on why so many conservative and moderate judges supported marriage
equality: “it is not the Constitution that changed, but the knowledge of what
it means to be gay or lesbian,” to which we should add transgender, nonbinary,
or queer. Kitchen v. Herbert, 961
F. Supp. 2d. 1181, 1203 (D. Utah 2013). In
Kitchen, Judge Shelby ruled that Utah’s exclusion of same-sex couples
from marriage was doubly invalid: it unconstitutionally denied those couples
their fundamental right to marry and was an unconstitutional
discrimination because of their sexual orientation. In the run-up to Obergefell,
most federal judges followed Judge Shelby on both the due process (liberty) and
equal protection claims—but few judges addressed the doctrinally simpler
argument that limiting marriage to different-sex couples is discrimination
because of “sex,” which the Supreme Court treats as a quasi-suspect
classification. By analogy to Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967),
which treated discrimination against different-race couples as race
discrimination, scholars and litigators for decades have maintained that
discrimination against same-sex couples is sex discrimination. Koppelman and Robinson lament that the
marriage equality movement was not as committed to the sex discrimination
argument for same-sex marriage as it might have been. In this response, we want to situate their
lament in the historical context of our book and to suggest how that argument
creates opportunities and conflicts that the commentators in this symposium
have productively addressed. In
1971, Jack Baker and Mike McConnell, the first “gay marriage” celebrities, made
the sex discrimination argument to the Supreme Court by analogy to Loving,
and Michael Withey’s brief for John Singer and Paul Barwick in Washington
developed its sociological contours in greater detail. Not a single judge gave it a second thought
in the 1970s, and marriage cases dried up during the early years of AIDS. When Chief Justice Ron Moon and Justices
Steve Levinson and Paula Nakayama of the Hawai‘i Supreme Court did accept the
sex discrimination argument in Baehr v. Lewin, 852 P.2d 44, 52 (Haw.
1993), their ruling was ridiculed and abandoned by liberals as well as
conservatives, and rejected by an overwhelming popular majority, in the Aloha
State. Beth
Robinson argued the Vermont marriage equality case. A student of Robin West and
Catherine MacKinnon, she was devoted to the sex discrimination argument, and
Shannon Minter backed her up with a powerful amicus brief from the National
Center for Lesbian Rights. But the argument bombed in a moot session and
ultimately attracted only the vote of Justice Denise Johnson in Baker v.
State, 744 A.2d 864 (Vt. 1999). In Goodridge
v. Department of Public Health, 798 N.E.2d 941 (Mass. 2003), the advocates successfully
emphasized the Baker argument that marriage equality was required even
under rational basis review, and the sex discrimination argument earned a shout
out only from Justice John Greaney. In
the California Marriage Cases, 183 P.3d 384 (Cal. 2008), Minter
prioritized the sex discrimination argument, but his co-counsel Terry Stewart
believed that it would not win the case—and she was right. Chief Justice Ron George wrote for a 4-3
marriage equality majority, yet the sex discrimination argument was the only
one he rejected. All
of this is in the book, and it demonstrates why one of us in 1996 felt that the
sex discrimination argument was logically valid and normatively compelling—but that
it would not be the winning constitutional argument, as it was incomprehensible
to non-feminist judges and did not reflect the priorities of most sexual
minorities. Almost all uncloseted gay
men and lesbians felt that sexual orientation discrimination was wrong, but only
a minority believed they were also being discriminated against because of sex. They were not alone. What the book also demonstrates is that
mainstream judges in the late twentieth century viewed gay people through the
lens of sexuality and not through the lens of gender. (In 1997, one of us [Eskridge] teamed up with
Nan Hunter to publish a casebook to undermine this idea: Sexuality, Gender, and the Law.) From
Outlaws to In-Laws also
provides an inside story of how the U. S. Supreme Court gradually came to accept
this line of thinking, and we shall now elaborate on that behind-the-curtain
account—not to say that the sex discrimination argument was anything but an
excellent argument, but to demonstrate the complexities of securing rights
through constitutional litigation. In
or around 1998, one of us collaborated with Justice Frank Iacobucci of the
Supreme Court of Canada to present materials on rights for gay people for a
conference of judges from all around the world.
We highlighted the marriage as well as consensual sodomy issues being
discussed in Canada, the United States, and other constitutional
democracies. Iacobucci and Eskridge
presented materials on the sex discrimination argument for gay rights. In our oral presentation to the judges, our
focus was the sex discrimination argument.
Aside from Iacobucci, few of the judges “got it,” but they listened
politely. A U.S. Supreme Court Justice
wondered why discriminating against a gay couple for marriage purposes was not
just “sexual orientation” discrimination, and not “sex” discrimination? Inspired
by Koppelman’s work, Eskridge explained the Loving analogy: if it is race discrimination to bar a white
man from marrying a black woman (while allowing him to marry a white woman),
then it is sex discrimination to bar a man from marrying a man (while allowing
him to marry a woman). The American
judge still didn’t get it—the first is racism and white supremacy, the second
is homophobia and not sexism. So, it’s
apples and oranges, sighed the exasperated jurist. Eskridge tried one more time: Steve can marry Cathy but not Carl. If Steve were Susan, she could marry Carl.
“Oh, I get it,” exclaimed the American jurist, “well no one is every going to
buy that argument.” Being
a Canadian intellectual, Iacobucci was stunned, but Eskridge was not too
surprised. It was a matter of
framing. In the United States at the end
of the millennium, even liberals with gay friends viewed the social group
through the lens of sexuality. Sure,
they understood that you can’t say “gay” without saying “sex,” and some
liberals understood lesbians through the lens of gender as well as sexuality. But the lives and identities of gay and
bisexual men were filtered through the lens of sodomy (acts) and not the
identity of their sexual partners. Some younger judges like Denise Johnson,
Steve Levinson, and Paula Nakayama understood the pervasive interconnection
among sexuality, gender, and the law—but they were a minority. When
the U.S. Supreme Court overturned the Texas Homosexual Sodomy Law in Lawrence
v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003), the Justices were aware that two Texas state
judges had declared the law an unconstitutional sex discrimination and that the
Texas judiciary had immediately rebuked them. See Lawrence v. Texas, 41
S.W.3d 349, 357-59 (Tex. App. en banc 2001), superseding 2000 WL 729417 (Tex.
App. 2000) (opinion withdrawn, but its author dissented from the en banc for
this reason, 41 S.W.3d at 366-75 [Anderson, J.]). The sex discrimination argument went nowhere
with the U.S. Supreme Court, and not just because advocates gave it little
emphasis. Since the early 1990s, Justice Anthony Kennedy had been determined to
overrule the Court’s infamous sodomy law opinion in Bowers v. Hardwick (1986),
and he, like concurring Justice Sandra Day O’Connor, viewed the law as
implicating sexual acts and sexuality-based identities (i.e., “homosexuals”),
not as implicating sex- or gender-based identities. Briefs supporting the challengers, including
Eskridge’s Cato amicus brief, emphasized the liberty argument over the sex
discrimination argument because a freedom-of-choice holding would sweep away
all consensual sodomy laws, not just the ones that discriminated because of sex
or sexual orientation. In
2003, Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg understood and, we think, agreed with the sex
discrimination argument for gay rights, because she (alone on the Court)
understood the normative underpinnings of the argument: anti-homosexual measures advanced the
historical entrenchment of rigid gender roles—the patriarchal ideology she had
condemned in the VMI Case, United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515 (1996). In short, RBG comprehended how homophobia was
an instrument of sexism. Yet she joined
the Kennedy opinion, which she enriched by encouraging him to include equal
protection analysis that complemented his liberty claims. As
Ginsburg told us before her death, the main reason she joined the Kennedy
opinion was that she, together with John Paul Stevens, David Souter, and Steve
Breyer, had an informal agreement to let Tony Kennedy (a Catholic Republican)
speak for all of them in gay rights cases, without special concurring
opinions. They wanted him to have pride
of authorship for written work they knew would bring him great praise from the
media and from academics such as us. But
a secondary reason for her acquiescence was that an opinion (majority or
concurring) bringing the sex discrimination argument “out of the closet” would
play into Nino Scalia’s hands, because all anti-gay laws would become
immediately suspect, à la the VMI Case.
Sounding the alarm to his Fox News and Federalist Society base, Scalia
announced in Lawrence that once “homosexuals” were no longer outlaws and
criminals, their taste for equal treatment would not be satiated until they had
marriage rights, which was way too much for the country to swallow. (Cassandra-like, he was right about that. Iacobucci and his colleagues were in 2003 pressing
Canada toward nationwide marriage equality.)
As
she had demonstrated in her work on sex discrimination in the 1970s, RBG was
committed to full equality but pragmatically believed that equality came on
cat’s feet and not overnight. In 2003,
the country had largely been persuaded not to attribute mental illness or
criminality to lesbians, gay men, and bisexuals, but overwhelming majorities
did not consider them marriage material. Thus, the sex discrimination argument
went too far in 2003 and for years later. Like presidential candidate Barack Obama as
late as 2008, Ruth Ginsburg felt the country needed a period of equality
practice before the sex discrimination argument could assume its legitimate
place in constitutional advocacy. On
the strength of arguments grounded in the fundamental right to marry and the
irrationality of anti-gay discrimination, equality practice proceeded apace between
2003 and 2015. Marriage equality
progressed from one state to all 50 in a dozen years. The value of state-by-state equality practice
was to bring committed same-sex couples, many raising children, to the public’s
attention; attention to the truth and consequences of their lives confounded
longstanding anti-gay stereotypes and put marriage equality skeptics on the
defensive. Every time people saw that gay marriage did not torpedo the
institution—not a single “traditional” marriage fell apart because of Goodridge—the
doomsday scenarios outlined by skeptics took a hit. Importantly,
a central feature of the post-2003 marriage debate was the steady rise of
gender and complementarity, and the corresponding eclipse of sexuality and
deviance, as its focus. Marriage
equality opponents read the tea leaves (precisely quantified by polls): they would lose moderates if they depicted
lesbian and gay Americans as sexualized monsters or depraved child molesters,
as almost everyone knew normal “homosexuals.” Respectable intellectuals such as Maggie
Gallagher and David Blankenhorn replaced homophobic zealots such as Alan Sears
and Robert Knight as the intellectual leaders of the opposition, and the new
messaging was that gays were great, but they didn’t fit the gendered
institution of marriage. By
2003, the main argument emerging among “traditional family values” litigators and
with conservative judges was that rascally heterosexuals needed marriage
because they were so irresponsible that their child-producing intercourse had to
be channeled toward legal commitments; because “the gays” planned their
children and so didn’t need marriage so much, it was okay to limit the
institution to those most in need for its discipline. We thought this was a very odd argument, but
we appreciated that it was way nicer to our kind than the “depraved, diseased,
and predatory sex criminals” arguments of the 1990s. Unfortunately, the responsible procreation
argument was often accompanied by an argument that was even more clearly
gendered: every child needed a father,
as the claim was usually expressed, because every child benefitted from role
models of both sexes. Some versions of
the role model argument did dismiss lesbian and gay couples as “bad parents,”
but this claim was lambasted by scientists and falsified by examples of good
parenting that people could see with their own eyes. At
the same time the marriage equality skeptics were falling back on gender role
and complementarity as their Maginot Line, the marriage equality advocates saw
their task as not only reframing the public’s understanding of sexual
minorities, but as reframing the purpose of marriage. Pioneered by the Vermont, Massachusetts, and
Connecticut advocates, the mantra was “Love Makes a Family” (the formal name
taken by Ann Stanback’s Connecticut group in 1999). The point of marriage is not biological
procreation—children can be adopted or created by assisted reproductive technologies
NeJaime discusses—but is rather interpersonal commitment. Same-sex couples are just as interested in
that as straight couples, and they raise children capably as well. Between
1971 and 2015, the audience for this Love Makes a Family understanding of
marriage expanded almost every year. And
it expanded for Ginsburgian reasons:
women with jobs and careers were not so willing to assume traditional
gender roles, and men were giving some ground; women were also having fewer
children, having them later, using assisted reproductive technologies, and were
increasingly raising kids with whom they had no biological connection. At the same time gay families were looking
more like “traditional” nuclear families with children, straight families were
looking more like gay “families we choose” (Kath Weston’s term). For
these reasons, as RBG and Obama predicted, public opinion was swiftly pivoting
in favor of marriage equality by 2009.
Appreciation for gender variety helped pave the way for Obergefell and
ensured greater cogency for the sex discrimination argument. Chief Justice Roberts treated it as a serious
point during the Obergefell oral argument, and Justice Kennedy had
raised it during the oral argument in Hollingsworth v. Perry, 570 U.S. 693
(2013). Justice Breyer was on board, and
the younger Justices, Sonia Sotomayor and Elena Kagan, thoroughly understood
the sex discrimination argument for marriage equality. So
why did that argument not carry the day in Obergefell? For better or for worse, the answer lies in
the idiosyncratic nature of judicial review, whose contours are influenced by
the particular commitments and frameworks for the nine people who happen to sit
on the Supreme Court at any given time.
At the Obergefell conference, four Justices did not think
marriage equality was required by the Constitution, four thought it required by
the Equal Protection Clause, and one (Tony Kennedy, of course) focused only on
his libertarian reading of the Due Process Clause. Because the implicit bargain within the
pro-gay block meant that Kennedy would write the opinion for the Court, it
meant the liberals were stuck with a liberty-loving and marriage-celebrating
majority opinion. RBG substantially wrote the equal protection paragraphs and
sold them to the Kennedy chambers. We
know from Court insiders that none of the Justices was pushing the sex
discrimination argument in Obergefell.
For Koppelman-Robinson reasons, we were surprised, but Justice Ginsburg
solved the riddle in a conversation with Eskridge: they all knew the Title VII and Title IX
cases with LGBT plaintiffs making the sex discrimination argument were
percolating up through the federal courts all over the country, and the
Justices were reluctant to predetermine the results in those cases without
thorough briefing and deliberation.
Roberts, Kennedy, and Ginsburg were all Harvard-educated legal process
institutionalists and loath for the Court to address constitutional issues that
were not “ripe” (an idea that Harvard-educated Felix Frankfurter and Alex
Bickel made famous in legal circles). As
RBG anticipated, the issue did arrive at the Court in Clayton County v.
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020), where the Ginsburg liberals were joined by
Roberts and an arch-textualist newcomer, Neil Gorsuch, who inherited the
Kennedy role as the Republican author of a sweeping LGBTQ+ rights opinion. Bostock held that Title VII’s bar to
job discrimination “because of sex” protects lesbian, gay, and transgender
employees from discrimination because of the sex of their partners or their
gender identities. Advertised
as an exercise in original public meaning, Gorsuch’s opinion for the 6-3 Court started
with a mechanical cut-and-paste approach to text, which in this case did
benefit the plaintiffs. But halfway
through the opinion, Gorsuch revealed that he understood the Ginsburg-Koppelman
reading of the marriage cases, that rigid gender roles are at the heart of both
sex discrimination jurisprudence and the disadvantages suffered by gender and
sexual minorities. (The turning point in
the majority opinion was its analysis of Bob and Hannah, hypothetical workers penalized
because they were not sufficiently masculine and feminine, respectively.) Both the formal and the conceptual claims
adopted in Gorsuch’s opinion struck the dissenters and most academics as
applicable to Title IX and other sex discrimination statutes, not to mention
the Equal Protection Clause. (In the
dying days of the Trump Administration, its Department of Justice produced an
internal memorandum bemoaning Bostock and offering a narrow view of its
logical implications.) As
Eskridge and Koppelman argued in their amicus brief, Bostock was an
analytical and social sequel to the marriage equality litigation. Sexuality,
gender, and the law have been inevitably wedded together by the marriage
equality debate. The rights of LGBTQ+
people are linked to the rights of women, and vice-versa. This partial convergence creates or
solidifies all sorts of linkages that have previously been obscure or
marginalized (by us as well as others).
Consider a few that are especially important for ongoing debates. To
begin with the most important point, made in the past by Derrick Bell Jr. and
Catherine MacKinnon, formal equality rests upon and papers over a social
foundation of gross inequality. As Cahn
and Carbone have documented in Red Families v. Blue Families (2010) and
subsequent work, marriage has increasingly become a preserve for the
well-to-do. In our book, Paula
Ettelbrick was the prophet who foresaw, in the 1980s, that marriage equality
would not benefit many lesbians, gays of color, and working class or poor
sexual and gender minorities. The family
law pluralism NeJaime advances might have similar limitations, as second-parent
adoption and assisted reproductive technologies are more easily utilized by well-to-do
LGBTQ+ persons than by those without resources.
One of the great laments in our book is that more states have not
adopted Colorado’s 2009 designated beneficiaries law, which creates an
inexpensive, easy-to-use menu for unmarried couples of all orientations to have
some of the safety-net benefits of marriage.
Cahn
and Carbone astutely observe that the marriage equality debate allowed
conservatives to “blame the gays” for the decline of marriage, and thereby to
deflect attention away from income inequality as the culprit. Many Americans are too poor to get
married. David Blankenhorn, once a
leading critic of marriage equality, agrees with Cahn and Carbone and advocates
safety net reform and income redistribution.
These are the best government programs to actually revive marriage—but Blankenhorn
has been shunned by most religious groups and virtually the entire conservative
establishment because of his abandonment of the campaign against marriage
equality and his insufficient interest in preserving traditional gender roles. Another
intersection of feminism and gaylaw involves the interaction of acts,
identities, and self-expression. As
Simone de Beauvoir famously wrote, one is not born a woman, it is what one
becomes.[1] Transgender women illustrate this proposition
most dramatically, but it applies just as much to cisgender, bisexual, and
lesbian women—and the general idea of gender construction applies to gay men,
bisexuals, transgender men, nonbinary persons, and queers. Following Beauvoir and American pioneers such
as Elizabeth Cady Stanton and Margaret Sanger, most feminists today understand
the linkage among reproductive freedom, nondiscrimination because of gender
role as well as biological sex, and consciousness-raising and expression of
independence. Following Frank Kameny,
Del Martin, Phyllis Lyon, and Phyllis Frye, most LGBTQ+ persons today
understand the linkage among sexual liberty, nondiscrimination because of
gender role (including sexual orientation), and freedom to express themselves
by coming out and by their attire. The
flip side of the connection among acts, identity, and self-expression is that
many Americans identify with gendered religious traditions, the expression of
which (from their point of view) requires dissociating from nonprocreative
marriages, abortion choice, and even contraceptives. The religious liberty of these Americans and
their institutions often runs up against equal treatment of women and LGBTQ+
Americans; freedoms for gender and sexual minorities may come at the cost of
equality for religious persons. These
are the famous liberty-equality clashes that NeJaime and Wilson explore in
their influential scholarship—but from largely opposing viewpoints. NeJaime argues against most religion-based
discrimination impinging on women’s reproductive freedom and gay people’s
workplace and marriage equality. Wilson argues in favor of religious allowances
on the face of anti-discrimination laws, similar to the ones we describe for
New York’s Marriage Equality Act of 2011.
With
NeJaime, we strongly oppose sex discrimination of any sort in government
programs, including the foster care state program before the Supreme Court in Fulton
v. City of Philadelphia (decision expected 2021). With Wilson, we favor religious allowances
that permit behind-the-scenes opting out, such as Utah’s allowing county clerk
employees to hand off same-sex marriage applications to co-workers, so long as
such applications were handled as seamlessly as all others. Eminent First Amendment scholars are divided
on the legal resolution of the wedding vendor cases, abortion and contraception
provisions in employer health plans, and adoption placements by agencies
licensed by the state (but not contract parties paid by the state to be
agencies in government programs). Our
book advocates legislation, like the famous 2015 Utah anti-discrimination and
religious liberty law, a “statute of principles,” to address these issues. We have little confidence that unelected,
unaccountable judges framing these issues through normative rather than neutral
lenses are the best officials to strike the balance—and we have no more faith
that law professors are any better, and they may be worse because they are even
less accountable. For years, we have
joined Wilson in urging state legislatures to replicate Utah’s deliberative
process (bringing together religious groups, LGBTQ+ organizations, and
businesses to work out principled accommodations), and we urge the Biden
Administration to support legislation at the federal level. Although Title VII now protects gender and
sexual minorities from discrimination, Gorsuch’s opinion for the Court said
that faith-based allowances would be evaluated in light of the Religious
Freedom Restoration Act of 1993, which protects at least some religious
employers that would deny some benefits and perhaps even employment to their
LGBTQ+ workers. Hence, there ought to be
incentives on all sides of the debate to work on measures that accommodate
religious liberty while recognizing or expanding equality for sexual and gender
minorities.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |