Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts An Unnecessary Conflict?
|
Thursday, July 16, 2020
An Unnecessary Conflict?
Guest Blogger For the symposium on Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs Religious Liberty? The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020).
Steven D. Smith
Andy Koppelman makes it clear
from the outset that people like me are not his book’s primary audience; we are
more in the nature of intended beneficiaries.
Andy mainly wants to persuade people on the Left that religious
conservatives, though tragically misguided in our beliefs (especially on
matters of sexual morality), are not necessarily evil, and that society can
make some space for us in the public square instead of shunting us into the
shadows like out-and-out racists.
So I should be appreciative; and
I am. Andy exudes a genuine magnanimity
of spirit that is rare these days. He
also demonstrates real courage, because some of his pleas and positions could
render him repellent in his own circles.
(Indeed, I’m afraid that as an old-time liberal– i.e. as a vigorous
proponent of pluralism and free speech-- he is already falling behind.) If there is any hope of healing the
frightening polarization that afflicts our society, that hope rests on people
like Andy.
Also, I find his analysis
persuasive. Not all of it, of
course. I am profoundly unpersuaded by
the arguments in Chapter 5 (the Masterpiece Cakeshop chapter) and
Chapter 6 (the Hobby Lobby chapter). But those issues have been thoroughly
debated, and Andy and I have already exchanged arguments on these points at
length, in private and occasionally in public.
So I won’t devote this limited space to rehashing those arguments yet
again.
Instead, I want to underscore a
couple of more implicit but ultimately more consequential differences. These differences have to do with what kind
of species we are– with philosophical anthropology, as some people put it– and
with our historical situation.
The Liberal
Framework
Andy seems to me to operate
basically on liberal assumptions. (No
surprise there.) For one thing, he
treats human beings essentially as interest-seeking animals. Not in any crass sense: Andy recognizes that
people have moral and religious commitments, which inform and shape our
interests. But he urges early on that we
should not get too hung up on our conflicting “principles” and should instead
focus on our “interests.” The overall
goal is or ought to be to achieve our interests as fully as possible. In a pluralistic situation, this will involve
trade-offs and compromises, which will be worked out mainly on the basis of
pragmatic assessments of what is workable, etc.
Andy also seems to assume as
secure a traditionally liberal institutional framework for the working out of
these compromises. By that I mean a
framework constituted by rule of law, a commitment to the equality of citizens,
a government that is neutral at least toward religion, a strong commitment to
free speech, and a genuine commitment to pluralism. Andy knows that these liberal commitments are
imperfectly realized: conservatives fail to embrace the full implications of
equality, he thinks, and people on the Left– the book’s intended audience– have
tended in recent years to underappreciate free speech and pluralism. The remedy for these shortcomings is to call
people back to the pluralistic liberal ideal– which is basically what the book
tries to do.
As it happens, I have
considerable sympathy for this approach.
The interest-seeking conception does capture a vitally important
dimension of who we are. And the liberal
framework may well be– or may have been?-- the best arrangement for
promoting human freedom and flourishing in a pluralistic situation (even if
that framework depends on benign fictions, like neutrality, and
question-begging truisms, like equality).
There are passages in Andy’s book that warmed my quasi-liberal heart in
an almost nostalgic way. Wasn’t it
wonderful when, back in the day, our elites used to recite– maybe they actually
believed– Voltaire’s “I will defend to the death . . .” etc.?
For someone in this liberal mood,
the details of Andy’s proposals may be debatable, but the overall approach
seems so eminently sensible that it is hard to understand why anyone would
resist it. Which, ironically, in itself
provokes a serious doubt. That is
because, as Andy himself makes clear, it seems that many people today– maybe
even most people, at least among the more active participants– do resist
his approach. Thus, Andy presents
himself, not implausibly, as representing a small moderate middle besieged by
intolerant conservatives on the Right and intolerant progressives on the Left.
So, why are so many people so
resistant to Andy’s so sensible approach?
Wondering about
the assumptions
My suggestion is that Andy’s
basic liberal assumptions are no longer the pertinent ones. That fact may be regrettable. But, as they say, it is what it is.
More specifically, in addition to
being interest-seeking animals, we are also, and more fundamentally, “moral
believing animals” who feel driven to live in harmony with some overall view of
the nature and meaning of things. The
idea is expressed in Chesterton’s dictum that “the most practical and important
thing about a man is still his view of the universe. . . . [T]he question is
not whether the theory of the cosmos affects matters, but whether in the long
run, anything else affects them.”
People constituted in this way
understandably prefer to live in a community that reflects, or at least is
friendly toward, their “view of the universe.”
So long as they feel secure in that respect, people may not think about
that view so much as assume it: their daily activities, and their politics, may
be mostly directed to their “interests.”
Liberalism and pragmatic interest-seeking may work pretty well in such a
situation. But when people begin to
perceive themselves to be in a community that is hostile to their view of the
universe, or to their fundamental faith, their deeper commitments may come into
play. This is our situation today, I
think– for religious conservatives, certainly, but for many others as well.
Thus, as Robert Bellah’s
influential work on civil religion showed, through much of our history
Americans understood their national community in basically biblical terms. This understanding evolved: it started out as
generically Protestant but over time developed into Will Herberg’s Protestant-Catholic-Jew. In that environment a Supreme Court majority,
speaking through Justice Douglas of all people, could say, “We are a religious
people whose institutions presuppose a Supreme Being.” The Court could say this as if it were noting
some self-evident truth.
By the 1960s, though, as Bellah
also explained, the long-standing “civil religion” was falling apart. And since that time, the various parties have
been struggling, in increasingly acrimonious fashion, to define what sort of
nation we live in– what its defining philosophy or fundamental principles and
commitments are. Its real
principles and commitments, as opposed to axiomatic but “empty” vessels like
“equality” that have to have their content poured into them from other more
substantive sources. (See Peter Westen,
etc.) And because communities are
“imagined” (as Benedict Anderson explained), and because such imaginings arise
from and coalesce around public symbols, many of the most contentious battles
of our time are to a significant extent battles over symbolism.
In some cases, as in
controversies over statues or crosses, the matters are almost purely
symbolic. In other instances, such as
controversies over wedding cakes or contraception, there are more practical
“interests” involved as well. Even so,
we misunderstand these controversies if we hone in on the conflicting
“interests” but fail to recognize that the community-constituting symbolism is
an important dimension– for many, probably the most important dimension– of
these disputes. Such controversies are,
to quote Chesterton again, battles of “creeds masquerading as policies,” and if
we debate only the policies but neglect the community-constituting creeds, we
miss what is really going on.
Similarly, we should not be
surprised if people on both sides of a dispute are unreceptive to proposed
compromises that offer what might seem like acceptable or at least debatable
trade-offs on the “interests” but that neglect to notice the weighty or
weightier symbolic dimensions of the controversies.
Why it matters
I have noted that people prefer
to live in a community that is hospitable toward their view of the
universe. This is not just a matter of
psychological comfort. People fear that
a community constituted on a view hostile to theirs will, at least over time,
work to disadvantage or marginalize them in concrete ways. This fear is entirely reasonable. And despite (or maybe because of) his
conciliatory intentions, Andy’s book is likely to reenforce it.
Thus, Andy argues that Christian
conservatives like Jack Phillips ought sometimes to be accommodated. As noted, his argument is primarily against
people who think the Phillipses of the world should not be accommodated at all;
so Christians presumably ought to appreciate Andy’s intervention. And I do.
Even so, in the end, the accommodation Andy offers is remarkably
meager. Almost negligible.
In the wedding vendor cases, a
very narrow exemption would be available to a Jack Phillips on terms that Andy
comes close to admitting will in practice render the exemption
meaningless. Andy notes that Phillips
himself was subjected to death threats and vandalism. A business cannot operate under such
conditions. But such reprisals will
predictably be inflicted on virtually any baker or photographer or florist who
makes a public announcement that he or she will not do same-sex weddings; and
it is hardly comforting to be told that this could be a viable compromise if
everybody would just respect the law.
Because (some) people just won’t.
More generally, Andy opposes
accommodating religious believers in ways that would impose costs or harms on
third parties. Apparently it is fine to
impose (sometimes massive) costs on others to accommodate things like physical
or psychological disabilities, but not to accommodate deeply-held religious
convictions. This principle would still
allow for accommodation in relatively trivial cases where the authorities are
restricting religion just out of orneriness.
(Like the prison authorities who forbade Muslims to wear quarter-inch
beards.) But in almost all cases of
consequence, accommodation of religion will involve some third-party costs–
thus precluding accommodation on Andy’s principle. (I have yet to hear a satisfying explanation
for why the long-standing exemption of religious pacifists from military
service would be permissible under this principle.)
Finally, religious conservatives
will not be reassured by Andy’s repeated statements that their traditional
sexual morality is “gravely and tragically wrong,” that it is “deplorable that
they believe what they believe,” and that “[t]hey should be ashamed of
themselves and repent.” (126) To be clear, I don’t intend this observation
as a criticism. I understand that Andy
is being his refreshingly candid and colorful self, and also that he needs to
make such statements to assure his primary audience of his bona fides. And essentially, he is simply recognizing
that anyone who believes someone else is seriously mistaken will probably wish
that person would give up his or her misguided opinions. This wish need not be a manifestation of
hatred or contempt; it may instead be an expression of concern and even
love. Christians, as he recognizes, will
have similar wishes toward him.
Fair enough.
Even so, the fact that the
sentiment is sincere and not contemptuous only underscores the reality that if
Andy’s basic commitments come to be the official orthodoxy (whether or not
disguised as “neutrality” or poured into “equality”), then maybe– just maybe–
people with traditional religious views will occasionally be accommodated; but
the nation is inevitably going to attempt to discourage and defeat the
pernicious views– in its schools, in its laws, in its funding, in all of the
ways that government attempts to disfavor views that it find obnoxious. That is not a message in which religious
conservatives can find comfort.
All that said, I repeat that if
the polarization in the country is to be overcome, it will be with the help of
people like Andy-- and, more generally, with the restoration of the sort of
liberal framework he assumes. I happen
to think that this liberal framework is most securely grounded in the
generically biblical self-understanding that, per Bellah, characterized this
country through the mid-twentieth century.
But that is an argument for a different essay.
Steven D. Smith is Warren Distinguished Professor of
Law at the University of San Diego. You can reach him by e-mail at smiths@sandiego.edu
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |