Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Who’s the Nazi?
|
Sunday, June 14, 2020
Who’s the Nazi?
Guest Blogger For the symposium on Linda McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020).
Andrew Koppelman
Linda
McClain’s Who’s the Bigot? is an impressive survey of the uses of the term
“bigot” in debates about civil rights over the past fifty years. She has immersed herself in those debates,
and the stories, about how the rhetoric has shifted in that time, is
fascinating. The now-forgotten arguments
that were once made on behalf of racial segregation are an intellectual freak
show. My favorite: “Christ himself never lived an integrated
life, and although He knew His life on earth would be a model for all mankind,
when he chose His close associates, they were all white.” (118)(Of course, no
one knows what Jesus’s disciples looked like.)
McClain
shows how, in old debates about racial integration and modern ones about gay
rights, there is a perennial tendency for both sides to make accusations of
bigotry. Proponents of racial equality
were accused of being bigoted against Southern whites. Defenders of gay rights are accused of being
bigoted against conservative Christians.
McClain
thinks that there is value in “drawing analogies between past and present forms
of discrimination and exclusion,” in order to “point out how, over time, new
insights and evolving understandings have let to recognition that such
treatment is unjustified.” (209) But she thinks that the charge of bigotry is
“often needlessly provocative and groundless.” (209) One need not “portray
religious beliefs as a pretext” in order to argue “that there must be limits to
acting on such beliefs in the marketplace.” (209) She thinks that those limits helped bring
about progress: “If it isn’t 1964 anymore, that is due in part to not having
robust religious exemptions.” (203) The
implication is that, in contemporary debates over gay rights and religious
liberty, we should refuse exemptions.
But we should do it nicely, without accusations of bigotry.
I
take issue with McClain on two and a half issues. I’m not persuaded that the comparison with
1964 shows that we need to refuse religious exemptions today. I have a different analysis than she does of
the concept of bigotry (that kind of nerdy nitpicking is only half an issue),
and I think that the weaknesses of her analysis lead her to be too charitable
to people on the left who now deploy the charge of bigotry against religious
conservatives. Her account of bigotry
understates how toxic the charge is.
It is a truth universally acknowledged that there
could not and should not have been religious exemptions from the Civil Rights
Act of 1964. “Racial segregation in the
marketplace and elsewhere likely would have persisted had legislatures and
courts allowed broad religious exemptions.” (203) From this one might infer –
many do infer – that that those who refuse to facilitate same-sex marriages are
not entitled to even the mild, defeasible presumption of accommodation that
America has often extended to conscientious objectors. One might also infer that, as in 1964, the
stakes are high enough to justify a state effort to stamp out the subculture
that embraces these hateful views.
But this misunderstands the situation the country
faced in 1964. One need not take
heterosexism less seriously than racism in order to understand the uniqueness
of our situation then.
America has a long tradition of accommodating
religious dissenters. As a general
matter, the law should not strive to stamp out any subculture and make its
members outcasts. Racism has been so
pervasive and destructive that these two principles are appropriately
overridden. The civil rights struggle
demanded coercive cultural reconstruction, especially but not only in the
states of the former Confederacy.
The question is not simply whether people are acting
on the basis of repugnant ideas. There
are a lot of repugnant ideas around. It
is whether there should be cultural war.
That question, like any decision to go to war, depends on prudential assessment
of likely consequences. In the case of
race, there has been progress, but the war isn’t over. Zero tolerance remains necessary. In the case of sexual orientation, war is
unnecessary and unlikely to improve matters.
Any religious accommodation rests in part on a bet
that it will not be invoked so often as to defeat the purpose of the law. There have been remarkably few wedding
vendors who have objected to same-sex marriage.
In 1964, there were too many racists who would have invoked any exemption. That’s not our world.
Look at the trends.
In 1997, 27% of Americans supported same-sex marriage. In 2017
it was 64%. Among Americans aged 18 to
29, in 2018
it was 79%. It is only 34% of white
evangelical Protestants, but even in that group, opposition has plunged from
71% in 2013 to 58% in 2017. Of white
evangelicals aged 18 to 29, a majority – 53% - are in favor. In 2017,
63 percent thought that homosexual sex is morally acceptable, compared with 40
percent in 2001. In short, there is a
cultural cascade taking place, but it is in the opposite direction.
The
rhetoric of bigotry has made it impossible to compromise.
McClain
raises, but never quite solves, several “puzzles about the rhetoric of bigotry:
whether it is the motive for or the content of a belief that makes it bigoted;
whether bigotry is simply shorthand for beliefs that are now beyond the pale;
and whether bigotry stems from a type of character, ‘the bigot,’ who has
specific moral and psychological traits, or whether we are all vulnerable to
being bigoted.” (6) All these are puzzles only if we think
bigotry has an essence whose content it is possible to determine by specifying
its necessary and sufficient conditions.
What she points to are not puzzles, but ambiguities: the term is
sometimes used in all of these ways. An
ambiguous word shouldn’t be puzzling: its meaning is simply ambiguous, and the
ambiguity will appropriately be resolved differently in different
contexts. The interesting question is
what the ambiguities tell us about the word and its use.
The
trouble lies in the notion that “bigotry” is a term with a definition, one that
has necessary and sufficient conditions.
On the contrary, it’s based on a prototype.
Think
of what happens when you call someone a Nazi.
The accusation is a metaphor, and calls attention to resemblances, but
it’s a mistake to look for definitional boundaries. What one is really saying is that the target
ought to elicit the same moral disgust as the historical Nazi does.
A
prototype can’t be defined. It has a
cluster of characteristics that one can reach for as the occasion demands.
The
prototypical bigot – the person whom the word brings to mind - is a thoroughly
repellent person, whose hatred of certain groups is baked into his
personality. He is a walking ball of
hatred, with an irredeemably evil character.
A prominent exemplar is Bob Ewell in To
Kill a Mockingbird, who beats and rapes his own daughter, frames an
innocent black man for the crime, and is killed while trying to murder two
children. He functions as a negative
model: you don’t want to be him.
What
the term bigot accomplishes is to assert that the fact that a person holds
certain beliefs shows that he is an awful human being, a Bob Ewell. That’s why the term is a conversation
stopper. What can you possibly say when
someone calls you a bigot? It is itself
an unfair stereotype of people who hold conservative religious beliefs about
sexuality. No wonder charges of bigotry
fly in both directions.
In Masterpiece
Cakeshop, a commissioner declared that “to me it is one of the most
despicable pieces of rhetoric that people can use to—to use their religion to
hurt others.” The Court observed that this disparaged the baker’s
religion “in at least two distinct ways: by describing it as despicable, and
also by characterizing it as merely rhetorical — something insubstantial and
even insincere.” The Court might also
have looked more closely at the phrase “use their religion.” It turns up a lot: in 2015, during one
exemption controversy, The New York Times
ran an editorial with this title: “In
Indiana, Using Religion as a Cover for Bigotry.” The implication is that the
baker was not really motivated by his religion.
He is using religion as a phony excuse for his malicious desire to
harm. One uses a tool, and is not used
by it.
McClain regards this language too forgivingly. Contemplating a few other deployments of the
“using religion” language, she writes:
“What does ‘using’ mean here? It
could mean that they knew that they were making pretextual arguments to justify
their self-interest. Or it could mean
that they read the Bible sincerely and confidently, but wrongly.” (212) The second reading is implausible. A person who is honestly mistaken is not
“using” his mistake. So “using one’s
religion” isn’t an innocent activity.
Another example of her excessive charity: a majority of the U. S.
Commission on Civil Rights declared that proposals for religious accommodation
“represent an orchestrated, nationwide effort by extremists to promote bigotry,
cloaked in the mantle of ‘religious freedom,’” and “are pretextual attempts to
justify naked animus against lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender
people.” Chairman Castro sought to
“ensure that religion never again be twisted” in this way.
McClain writes that this language “may imply that
the commissioners question the motives and sincerity of those who asserted the
beliefs; or it may mean that the commissioners think that such beliefs distort
true religion because they deny equality.” (185) Too generous again. What could “pretextual” mean other than that
these people are lying about what they believe?
The label of “pretextual” seems to rely on the idea
that no one could really believe this stuff.
But that notion evades the familiar problem of religious diversity. Other
people’s religious beliefs often seem obviously bizarre to us.
Many
decent people honestly embrace the sexual ethics that, they believe, their
religions have taught for centuries.
They take those teachings seriously.
They think that life and morality make no sense without a religious
basis. I disagree, but I disagree with a
lot of people about a lot of things. The
American right and left are notoriously polarized, but large parts of each are
certain that those who disagree with them are necessarily evil. It is exactly the kind of stupid stereotype
that is the natural target of the term “bigot.”
In the contemporary debate over gay
rights and religious liberty, there just aren’t a lot of Bob Ewells. Today, if
you use the term bigot in this context, there’s some danger that you are
one. Both sides ought to retire this
term. It’s a weapon rather than a tool
of reasoning, and it turns on its possessor, paralyzing his mind and making him
stupid.
Andrew Koppelman, John Paul Stevens Professor of Law
at Northwestern University, akoppelman@northwestern.edu, is the author of Gay
Rights vs. Religious Liberty? The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University
Press, June 2020).
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |