Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Shall We Break Up?
|
Thursday, May 14, 2020
Shall We Break Up?
Guest Blogger For the Symposium on Timothy William Waters's Boxing Pandora: Rethinking Borders, States, and Secession in a Democratic World (Yale University Press, 2020) and F. H. Buckley's American Secession: The Looming Threat of a National Breakup (Encounter Books, 2020). Robert Tsai In American Secession, F.H. Buckley has written a slim and breezy volume that pleads for recognition of the right to secede based on the compact theory of the U.S. Constitution and, bowing to the low prospects of that happening anytime soon, presents a menu of second-best solutions that might capture the spirit of secession without all of its pain. It’s a fun and quick read. The author is well read and jocular. Yet Buckley’s approach to the Constitution’s text and history is too cursory to be sound, and he glides over too many of the hardest normative questions raised by a right for people to exit a political community and take the marbles with them.
He repeatedly asserts that “the
constitutional originalist must . . . conclude that the states had a right to
secede” as if the answer is plain. But the answer isn’t obvious. Buckley
doesn’t adequately grapple with the text of the Constitution, which neither
establishes a right to secede nor prohibits it explicitly. Yet it does
expressly change the terms of political community, as well as its foundations. It
does so by dropping the Article of Confederation’s language of “confederation”
and the more strident rhetoric of state “sovereignty”—along with the power of a
single state to stop a constitutional amendment dead in its tracks—in favor of “the
people of the United States” forming a new government based entirely on a new
formula that gives no such veto power to any single state.
These changes, as Bruce Ackerman,
Akhil Amar, and many others have pointed out, reflect a powerful rejection of
the compact theory as the basis for self-rule in favor of an account of
sovereignty grounded in the “people of the several states.” The states retain
form and authority, but they have been dethroned in our political theory as the
genesis of sovereignty—it rests in the hands of the people themselves. At least
that’s what the Constitution seems to say and the Framers’s own example
demonstrates. Of course, it’s a separate question entirely how many people
remember or accept this move, and for that matter, what lessons later
generations might draw from this precedent.
But changing the rules collectively
once doesn’t mean that just anyone can change the rules again—or more
importantly, that one segment of the citizens can do so through unilateral
action. In fact, a self-executing right of secession would have greatly alarmed
most of the Framers, particularly the Federalists driving the project of
renewal, given their general mission to strengthen federal power as the primary
method of enhancing “a firm union.” It would also have worsened the problems of
faction with which they were intensely occupied if a single state could rattle
its saber and threaten to dissolve the union or depart every time it disagreed
with a piece of legislation or a president’s order.
Now, Buckley cites Federalist No.
43 as if it unquestionably settles the matter, but of course that pamphlet did
no such thing. Toward the end of that essay, Madison takes up the issue of why
the “Confederation . . . can be superseded without the unanimous consent” the
states. He invokes the nature of a “compact between independent sovereigns,”
which, according to well-established treaty principles, allows a party to it to
claim that the agreement has been “violated and void.” That’s correct given the
original terms of who entered into that agreement. Behind that contract
principle, of course, is the deeper right of self-governance rooted in natural
law. But Madison nowhere asserts that if the Constitution were approved based
on the new theory of self-governance, a single state or even a few disgruntled
states, can dissolve it.
Indeed, Madison insists, in a
letter dated January 1, 1833 to Alexander Rives, that “a rightful secession
requires the consent of the others, or an abuse of the compact.” The idea that
“a single State has a right to seceded, at will from the rest . . . would not,
till of late, have been palatable anywhere.” Even if secession could be done,
it would have be accomplished “without injustice or injury to the Community.”
Think of the “consequences,” including the dismemberment of territory. An
individual expatriate could not, for instance, “withdraw his portion of
territory from the common domain.”
In my
own writings, I have investigated how arguments about repudiation, withdrawal,
and other forms of self-organization derive from the language and rhythms of
popular sovereignty deployed by the Revolutionary generation. Claims concerning
a right of secession are certainly a part of that tradition. One of the best
recent treatments in this vein is Cynthia Nicoletti’s Secession on Trial,
but more on that in a minute. The point I want to stress for now is that it is
possible both that the original constitutional basis for nullification,
interposition, or secession is relatively weak (Buckley writes approvingly of
all three), and that Americans have still occasionally asserted that such extraordinary
remedies exist. The fact that some non-trivial number of citizens continue to
believe that secession is a legitimate solution for unhappiness is some
evidence supporting that right, but it’s not an originalist argument (at least
not one claiming to know the Framers’ intentions or the public meaning of
particular clauses); rather, it’s a very different argument based in some theory
of popular sovereignty.
It’s possible to make this kind of argument,
of course, but it’s incredibly tricky to do so. To really put your shoulder
into it, you’d have to entertain the possibility that the substance of the
Constitution isn’t just a matter of fidelity to the exact words inscribed in
1787 or 1868. Text doesn’t so much bind; it inspires. Instead, constitutional
meaning has largely always been, or at least in key respects today has become, a
product of some more intricate, though unruly, process through which
fundamental matters are contested. Coming up with a plausible account that authorizes
popular defiance or drastic reorganization that doesn’t seem like a
free-for-all is much harder than you think.
Buckley is right to point out that
everyone from James Buchanan to Joseph Story believed that the Union was
“perpetual” and could not be dissolved; Lincoln himself rejected the compact
theory once the slaveholding states began to take their leave. Others, however,
have taken a different view—most notably the fire-eaters who pushed their
slave-dependent societies to cut their losses after Lincoln’s election, and
based on a compact theory they never quite let go, to cut out. Buckley sides
with the latter. Constitutional meaning isn’t just a matter of judges adding up
all the people who think one way, and subtracting those who think another way.
Nicoletti’s painstaking take on the
treason trial of Jefferson Davis does a better job of showing how a legal proceeding
can be one way that a country attempts to work out an answer to such hard
problems. What she demonstrates is that constitutional politics sometimes makes
for strange bedfellows. In this instance, some Republicans cheered for Davis’s
lawyers because they felt that a judicial ruling that secession was legal would
strengthen the most stringent Reconstruction measures against “conquered
provinces.” Finally, Nicoletti shows us that constitutional crises often yield
unsatisfying answers that involve kicking the can down the road. Davis’s trial
ends because he receives a pardon; the Supreme Court eventually takes Lincoln’s
side of the debate in Texas v. White, but that hasn’t kept
ex-Confederates, New Afrikans, contemporary white nationalists, or proponents of
#CalExit from continuing to dream of self-liberation.
Since Buckley doesn’t spend much
time defending the right to secede, it seems that he actually isn’t all that
interested in inspiring new independent movements in America. It shows. At
times, the dark threat of armed secession seems like a rhetorical ploy to get
us to favor a devolution of political authority to states rather than
justifying speedier exit. Because after he discusses secession, he moves into
the heart of the book, which actually presents a case for why large political
communities have more problems than smaller countries. Buckley contends that
people who live in larger countries are less happy than those who live in
smaller ones, that large republics experience more corruption, and that the
representatives of small countries render policies that are more in line with
the needs of the citizens.
Most of these arguments we’ve heard
before, as they are the kinds of things that classical republicans and
certainly the anti-federalists once said. There’s truth here, but it’s also
worth noting that such arguments can prove too much: why not cities or counties
or even smaller units rather than states? It’s the logical place that a number
of secessionists, both old and new, have actually taken these arguments.
Calhoun’s own theory of secession was initially based on the plantation as the
most fundamental unit of society rather than the individual, the family, or the
state. In the Northeast and the West, property-rights militants, armed
ranchers, “constitutional sheriffs,” and others have argued that counties, single
neighborhoods, and even certain collectives have the right to withdraw from the
state or country.
It’s toward the end of American
Secession that Buckley finally arrives at what he really wants to get off
his chest: a proposal of “home rule” as “an exit option of sorts.” By then,
he’s tried to reassure us that even secession today is “politically correct,”
by which I take to mean that progressives and Democrats are open to it, just as
social conservatives and many Republicans are. This is part of Buckley’s
strategy of rescuing secession from its past association with slavery and
opposition to civil rights, as well as from modern ethno-nationalist movements.
It’s also a way of making states’ rights more palatable if it feels like the
only way to avoid civil war.
What would home rule mean in
America? Economically, it would allow each state to opt out of federal economic
regulations. Buckley acknowledges that this could lead to “a race to the bottom
in some ways,” with some states relaxing rules governing migrant labor or the
environment, just as states once fell over each other to enact the most
business-friendly laws when it came to workers’ rights. Buckley explicitly says
that states should be able to “opt-out of national equalization programs,” but the
part he doesn’t say out loud is that this would mean an effective reversal of
the New Deal and Great Society, which represented major intergenerational
achievements—not just social welfare programs, but also principles that have
changed what it means to be Americans.
To his credit, he acknowledges that
poverty would probably worsen in some places given parochial norms and
preferences, and that no federal measure to reduce wealth inequality could then
be effective to reverse widening inequality. He suggests that states that want
to maintain such programs can continue to do so, and people can vote with their
feet, but of course the most impoverished Americans would just be trapped where
they are.
As for civil and constitutional
rights, Buckley is totally comfortable with a state nullifying an
interpretation of the federal Constitution that it doesn’t agree with, whether
it has to do with religion, guns, abortion, or same-sex marriage. He doesn’t believe
that much would change—which seems incredibly optimistic—but he also doesn’t
take all that seriously the central question of what it means to be an American
in such a world if one could no longer expect a bundle of constitutional
rights, apart from the right to travel. What would keep us together if there
was no longer a common notion of historical struggle, national mission, and coherent
set of rights?
Robert L. Tsai is Professor of Law at American University.
You can reach him by e-mail at rtsai@wcl.american.edu.
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |