Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Constitutional Conflict (Almost) All the Way Down
|
Sunday, May 03, 2020
Constitutional Conflict (Almost) All the Way Down
Guest Blogger For the Symposium on Gerald Leonard and Saul Cornell, The Partisan Republic: Democracy, Exclusion, and the Fall of the Founders' Constitution, 1780s-1830s (Cambridge University Press, 2019).
After falling out of favor,
constitutionalism is enjoying a resurgence in American historical circles. For
those of us who have tilled this intellectual soil, this is a propitious development,
and one that makes the arrival of Gerald Leonard and Saul Cornell’s new book, The
Partisan Republic: Democracy, Exclusion, and the Fall of the Founders’
Republic, 1780s-1830s, timely. When fields, particularly one as
long-standing as constitutional history, attract renewed interest, expert
syntheses are especially valuable. They can provide original perspective on enduring
conversations while provoking new ones; take stock of our existing knowledge
while noting its current limits; and survey previous avenues of analysis while
fashioning new points of departure. This book realizes this promise. It offers
the finest succinct overview of the constitutional and legal history of the
early United States yet written, along the way reminding readers why this is
such a fertile and stimulating field of study.
By virtue of its synthetic prowess, The
Partisan Republic is sure to have a major impact on how the subject is
introduced to those new to its study. Condensing half a century of historical
development and integrating several distinct scholarly literatures into such a
tidy, highly readable volume is no small feat. Especially impressive is how
ably Leonard and Cornell integrate a more familiar top-down narrative of legal
and constitutional development with one from the bottom up—weaving together the
formal debates and disquisitions found in legislative halls, courtrooms, and
treatises with the muscular forms of popular political expression that
dominated the expanding world of partisan print, gave rise to new kinds of
public gathering and protest while invigorating traditional ones, and fueled
new techniques of politicking, campaigning, and political mobilization. Well-known
episodes such as the battle over Alexander Hamilton’s financial program, the
Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions, Marbury v. Madison, and the Missouri
Crisis are told alongside less familiar ones like Martin v. Commonwealth,
the Ohio Supreme Court’s ruling in Rutherford, and the New York Constitutional
Convention of 1821. Thomas Jefferson’s understanding of the Constitution and
republicanism is understood in contrast to John Taylor’s and William Manning’s.
This kind of integrated constitutional history is sorely needed. We still know
far too little about popular constitutionalism in the early republic (what we
do know is owed in no small measure to the authors’ own prior, important
work on the
subject) or how popular constitutionalism, across its many dimensions,
intersected with the kind of constitutionalism that manifested itself in James Madison’s
learned writings, the Washington administration, or the Marshall Court.
Leonard’s and Cornell’s book helps address these longstanding deficiencies
while calling attention to the continuing need for additional work.
Thanks to the authors’ deep learning,
the volume offers far more than compact synthesis, however. Its tight narrative
of constitutional conflict and change also advances an overarching argument sure
to provoke productive scholarly debate. That would be fitting, because if this
fine book is ultimately about one thing, it surely would be debate itself—the
deep and fundamental debate that roiled the early United States and transformed
it into a new kind of constitutional republic. The many meanings embedded in its
evocative title capture this essential story. The Partisan Republic
charts how one integrated vision of the Constitution and the republic was
supplanted by another. Echoing Gordon Wood’s The Radicalism of the American Revolution, Leonard and Cornell argue that the elitist republican
vision shared by most of the Constitution’s framers was challenged and ultimately
superseded by a more popular, democratically-minded vision of the nation’s
fundamental law. The republic thus came to be engulfed in and defined by the
kind of democratic partisanship and party politics that many of the Founders
had hoped to keep at bay. Unlike Wood’s account, however, Leonard and Cornell
assiduously emphasize the darker side of this process: how the ascent of white,
male democracy marched in lockstep with the exclusion of blacks, women, and
Native Americans from participation in the republic. The ascent of Jeffersonian
republicanism, but most especially Martin Van Buren’s Democratic Party that
grew out of it, led to the “full, explicit racialization of the American
constitutional order” (147) through the “legal entrenchment of white
democracy.” (175) The republic, in this regard, was itself partisan, promoting
some members at the stark exclusion of others.
Yet, the book’s title is fitting for
another reason still, one that best captures why debate is arguably its
defining theme. The Constitution itself, Leonard and Cornell insist, proved
both the source and object of the period’s acrimonious and transformative
partisanship. At a time when few thought the Revolution was truly over or
accepted the possibility of a loyal opposition, disputes often ran deep to the
very marrow of the constitutional order that Americans had only recently erected.
The early republic was no era of good feelings or broad consensus and the
Constitution in particular, new and untested as it was, proved to be a fount of
pronounced and fundamental disagreement. As Leonard and Cornell show so well,
bitter disputes that helped precipitate the drafting of the federal
Constitution in 1787 spilled over beyond ratification only to be deepened and
extended by fresh conflicts. For these reasons, the Constitution could not
stand above the conflict. The period’s partisanship did not unfold safely and
orderly in a space that the Constitution had created; more often than not, those
struggles contested the very confines of that space. Even if early
constitutional disputants commonly appealed to the Constitution’s authority,
their ways of doing so often betrayed radical disagreement over the very Constitution
to which they were appealing: its character, how it should be interpreted, and
its ultimate relationship to the sovereign people.
The rival forms of constitutionalism
that emerged from these fundamental divisions created the early republic’s defining
fault lines. And the history that Leonard and Cornell narrate becomes a story
of collision and its consequences: of how those competing ways of understanding
the Constitution smashed into one another to produce a constitutional republic
that few, in 1787, could have imagined. How Leonard and Cornell track the
debates generated by these early constitutional fault lines is among the most
invigorating and revealing features of their rich narrative.
As they explain, in the wake of
ratification, at least three distinct kinds of constitutionalism took shape: a
Federalist Constitution, a moderate Republican Constitution, and a radical
Republican Constitution. What most sharply divided these different varieties of
Constitutions was what Leonard and Cornell call “legalism”—or the extent to
which the Constitution ought to be conceived as a legal instrument that
incorporated standing legal principles and entrusted the judiciary with final interpretive
authority over its meaning. Federalists were the arch-defenders of the legalist
Constitution. They contended that the federal courts enjoyed unique authority to
determine the Constitution’s meaning and exploited that perceived authority in
an attempt to constitutionalize traditional common law rights to contract and
property. They especially embraced this judge-centered vision of constitutional
law after 1800, once their Republican opponents had taken control of the
federal government’s political branches and they found themselves confined to
the judiciary.
Republicans conceived of the
Constitution in a much different way, though among themselves they disagreed over
how completely to reject Federalists’ legalism. Radical, democratic-minded
Republicans vigorously championed a “populist Constitution” (113) built on an “antilegalist
ideology.” (84) They refused to accept that the Constitution was an
anti-democratic, legal instrument that smuggled in judge-made common law and
elevated the judiciary above the will of the sovereign people—who they believed
alone enjoyed final interpretive authority over the nation’s fundamental law. They
bristled at the notion that law’s purpose was to curb and constrict the
democratic energy that had been unleashed by the Revolution, and especially if
that meant unduly safeguarding minority rights to contract and property against
the will of the majority and the public good. These radicals accordingly sought
to free the Constitution from Federalists’ lawyerly grips, calling for
constitutional amendments that would bring appointment and removal of federal
judges under congressional control, the repeal of the Judiciary Act of 1801
(which had dramatically expanded the federal judiciary), and the impeachment of
the most outspoken and partisan Federalist judges. Moderate Republicans shared
many of the radicals’ misgivings with legalism, particularly the idea of
judicial supremacy. But, as Leonard and Cornell stress, the moderates valued the
role an independent judiciary played in the Constitution’s scheme of separated
powers and more generally respected the distinction between law and politics—even
if they agreed with the radicals that the latter ought to play a decisive role
in constitutional development. These constitutional divisions that separated
Federalists from Republicans and divided Republicans among themselves were not
merely interpretive; they turned on the very nature of the Constitution’s
content and its relationship to law.
Before and after 1800, these
distinct varieties of constitutionalism did battle, as illustrated in Leonard’s
and Cornell’s illuminating discussions of several crucial episodes: including
the conflict over the judiciary acts that culminated in Stuart v. Laird,
Marbury v. Madison, the failed attempt to remove Judge Samuel Chase,
debates over the constitutionality of a national bank and internal improvements
legislation that followed the War of 1812, and the Cherokees’ and John Marshall’s
(ultimately futile) efforts to hold the white democracy at bay in Worcester
v. Georgia. In perhaps the book’s best treatment, the decade-plus struggle
to bring resolution to the corrupt sale of Georgia’s Yazoo lands neatly pitted
the localist, democratic Constitution of popular will against the national,
legalist Constitution of judicial pronouncement, with the Supreme Court eventually
overruling the Georgia legislature’s exercise of popular constitutional review
(which had voided the corrupt land sales) in Fletcher v. Peck. “All of
these messy results,” argue Leonard and Cornell, “made clear that the meaning
of the Constitution would evolve in fits and starts, not as the working out of
a single principle but as the product of a fluid constitutional politics.”
(114) The Constitution would not be neatly worked out based on its own inner
logic; debate over the character of that very logic would fuel the politics
that drove its development.
Crucial aspects of each
constitutional vision survived these struggles, Leonard and Cornell contend.
The Federalist-minded judiciary maintained relative independence and was able
to defend, at least partially, many of its priorities. Nevertheless, the
emerging Democratic Party, which sprang from Republicans’ internal divisions
over legalism and came to speak for the radical defenders of popular
sovereignty, proved the dominant constitutional institution by the 1830s. This
meant, crucially, that during this long period the “operative meaning of the
Constitution depended on political and cultural development much more than on
constitutional text, established doctrine, and judicial pronouncements.” (208)
Those legal scholars who project a modern Court-centric view of the
Constitution backwards in time might take particular note of this contention. Yet,
Leonard and Cornell also stress that the courts, like all of the period’s constitutional
partisans, were never overwhelmed. In the end, the fundamental conflict that
defined the period lingered on, as “no dogma of constitutional authority would
ever grasp final victory.” (114)
Leonard and Cornell suggest, in
other words, that when it came to the early Constitution there was conflict
(almost) all the way down. The Constitution was accepted as supreme authority—meaning
the conflict did not run all the way to the bottom—yet most attempts to call
upon its authority only constitutionalized politics and politicized the
Constitution more deeply. This portrayal aligns, in important ways, with my own stated thinking
on the matter, and I certainly believe that it ought to frame further efforts to
understand the history of early national constitutional debate. It also helps
us better see the nature of the Founding and the Constitution, and how each relates
to the present, and I will briefly consider two particular ways in which The
Partisan Republic does so: in the first instance by challenging us to see
how poorly the Founding, on its own terms, fits our modern expectations; in the
second by urging us to think more deeply about the character of constitutional
agreement at the Founding and beyond.
The illuminating way in which Leonard
and Cornell portray early constitutional conflict encourages us to overcome the
enduring and ever potent desire to see the Founding as a tidy morality tale,
with well-defined heroes and villains, that can be easily translated into the
interpretive needs of the present. There has never been any shortage of
interest in identifying what the Founding just was so that its essential
meaning, and the moral to be taken from it, might be mobilized in the present.
The enduring debate over the Progressive interpretation of the Constitution—which,
for over a century,
has maintained that the Constitution was erected as a bulwark against democracy—has
richly enhanced scholarly understanding. Yet, too often it has devolved into a
loaded dispute over justice and equity, forcing interpreters to crudely choose
sides in the Founding era’s own struggles based on who we think deserves our
sympathies and, in turn, whether the original reasons for drafting the Constitution
are worthy of our esteem. A similar dynamic has fueled parallel efforts to
pinpoint the Founding’s fraught relationship with slavery, often by measuring
just how much aid and comfort
the Constitution provided the institution—controversy
over which just recently exploded surrounding the New York Times’s “1619
Project.” The hit Broadway sensation, Hamilton, has also prompted debate
over the Founding’s capacity to offer a usable past. The musical earned acclaim
for how its diverse casting inverted (and thus called attention to) the racial
hierarchies that have plagued the nation’s past, raising important questions
about who controls the narrative of history, and for how it turned Hamilton’s
life into an homage to the contributions of immigrants. Many historians joined
the chorus of praise. But some have condemned not just the musical’s historical
inaccuracies but its faux-wokeness,
reminding students of the period that the real Hamilton was at best a lukewarm
opponent of slavery, who held democracy at arm’s length, supported child labor,
tolerated his party’s anti-immigration policies, laid the groundwork for the
military-industrial complex, and, above all, extolled the virtues of a system
of financial capitalism destined to widen inequalities between rich and poor.
Perhaps reviving neo-Federalism is not so progressive after all. Meanwhile, in
law it of course has long been common to look to the Founding not just for
legal understanding but as a source of constitutional ideology—to ground a particular
brand of constitutional politics, and its assumptions about the size and reach
of government and the kinds of freedoms meant to be protected from it, in the
authority of the Founding.
At their best, each of these forms
of historical engagement have produced fruitful insights and provoked valuable
conversations. But the instinct to distill the Founding down to a distinctive
set of recognizable values is not without its costs. Not only does it tend to
flatten the period’s messy contours but, more problematic still and less widely
recognized, it runs the risk of presupposing that the early republic’s
constitutional politics are consonant with our own. Among The Partisan
Republic’s great strengths is how effectively it exposes this dissonance
between past and present.
It does this through its lucid
classification of the period’s competing constitutional ideologies, by forcing
readers to take full measure of the Federalist, moderate Republican, radical
Republican, and finally, Democratic Constitutions that vied for early
Americans’ allegiance. Any effort to categorize these Constitutions by the
standards of modern political dispute break down. As Leonard and Cornell
detail, Federalists favored an expansive national government capable of coping
with distinctly national problems. But they were also skeptical of, if not
downright hostile to democracy. While some among their ranks, such as James Wilson,
promoted democratic ideas, most others from Alexander Hamilton and John Adams
to Gouverneur Morris and Fisher Ames
were far less receptive. Thus, while the Federalist judiciary defended national
power against those who might revive the kind of devolved federalism known
under the Articles of Confederation, that same judiciary persistently favored
contract and property rights against what it regarded as the impulsive whims of
popular rule. Republicans and Democrats, especially their more radical
partisans, were more committed to the practice of democracy and more hostile to
elite pretensions and economic interests. But they assumed democracy went
hand-in-hand with weakening the federal government and championing states’
rights as well as starkly defining political participation based on gender and
race (which was among the reasons wealthy slaveholders often were not the immediate
target of their populist critiques). Federalists, as illustrated by the Alien
and Sedition Acts, were perfectly willing to clamp down on foreigners, yet,
they also proved more willing (however meagerly) to protect and even empower
marginalized groups. Meanwhile, even if Federalists were more committed to the
rule of property, their favored common law interpretive techniques presumed
that the Constitution incorporated vast swaths of unwritten content and thus
called for a more latitudinarian reading, one more capable of defending and
tapping into the Constitution’s full possibilities. Republicans and Democrats,
by contrast, were hostile to the common law and artful legal reasoning,
claiming that, when it came to the Constitution, sola scriptura would suffice,
thus tightly circumscribing its interpretation and use.
Labeling any one of these ideologies
liberal or conservative, progressive or libertarian (as we understand those
terms), without resorting to distortion, is all but impossible. In portraying
this complex constitutional history so lucidly and accurately, then, Leonard
and Cornell encourage us to do the hard work of familiarizing ourselves with
the period’s peculiar constitutional politics rather than forcing it to speak
to our own.
This is among the advantages of
seeing how the Constitution was an endless source of dispute in the early
republic. But, as Leonard and Cornell also imply, that conflict did not run the
entire way down. It is not difficult to imagine a slightly alternative history
in which Anti-Federalism persisted into the 1790s and a healthy cross-section
of the nation refused to accept the Constitution’s legitimacy. Yet, whether
Madison’s gambit to push through constitutional amendments in the First
Congress proved the difference-maker, the Second Convention movement quickly
collapsed and debate was subsumed under the Constitution’s authority. Even if
the depth of constitutional strife in the early republic was more pronounced
than many have been willing to see or accept, this emphasis also urges us to
better understand the character of the constitutional agreement upon against
which such divisive conflict was ultimately set. If when it came to the early
Constitution it was—to invoke an enduring allegory—turtles most of the way down, how ought we to conceive
of the bottom turtle upon which all of that fierce constitutional partisanship
rested? How do we make sense of the Constitution that took shape during this
formative age (and perhaps with which we still live), one that simultaneously functioned
as a source of unquestioned authority and yet such searching disagreement? Most
attempts at the time to defend what the Constitution was and required proved
divisive, so what kind of agreement lay beneath these disputes? Adequately
answering such complex questions would require an extensive analysis far beyond
what is possible here. But some preliminary thoughts might at minimum suggest
that these questions—fairly raised by the Constitution’s own history,
especially as told in The Partisan Republic—deserve fuller attention.
The simple answer would be that the
Constitution’s first users regarded it as an authoritative written text that
was open to a range of interpretations. They could agree on the source of
authority if not its exact meaning. But that effectively describes, in
different terms, what actually needs explaining. Because, as Leonard and
Cornell illustrate so skillfully, early understandings of constitutional text
and interpretation could lead to radically different places, depending on one’s
conception of, among other things, the relevance of existing forms of law and the
extent to which the Constitution recognized them. Rival accounts of what kind
of content was even in the Constitution thus complicated early efforts
to ground its interpretation, fueling the precise brand of fundamental debate
that Leonard and Cornell document so well. The Constitution that the Founding
generation agreed on, consciously or implicitly in their practices, was to be
found outside the bounds of known law and beyond putative recognition of an
authoritative text.
Possibly what early disputants really
agreed on, then, was a set of institutions, established under the Constitution,
through which existing and emerging disputes could be channeled. And, of course,
they did readily agree on this. Yet, as Leonard and Cornell repeatedly stress,
at no point during the period they investigate was their agreement on which
institution (if any) could resolve disagreements among them. More than this,
when invoking the Constitution, early disputants agreed that it was a higher
law that preceded and superseded those institutions. So their own arguments
betrayed something more than a functional description of government.
Perhaps instead what they agreed on was
an authoritative language of debate, a common set of argumentative resources. This
understanding flowed naturally from how the Constitution seemed to present
itself and what was known about its construction. In many ways, it was a series
of deferred disagreements—textual choices its framers had made to avoid controversy and help ensure
ratification that left subsequent generations to
have the debates that they had been unable to resolve. But were there inherent
limits to this language of debate? Was it all, in practice, endlessly
malleable? Leonard and Cornell, of course, argue that political and cultural,
rather than legal, developments primarily shaped the Constitution during the
early republic. Conflict over the Constitution ran sufficiently deep, they
suggest, that pragmatic accommodations, informal settlements, and other
essentially political resolutions provided the stability and order that the
Constitution’s putative legal meaning simply could not. This might indicate
that constitutionalism was largely a reflection of the urgency of certain
political needs and the measurement, at any given time, of certain partisans’
political strength. Yet, the Constitution remained authoritative, no matter its
intermingling with politics.
Maybe, then, the Constitution was
primarily a shared language of debate that recorded a series of what were
fundamentally political resolutions. Those could always be revised and reworked
through subsequent political disputes, though, once recorded in the language of
constitutionalism, not without significant effort. Perhaps this dynamic—in
which the Constitution both controlled and yet was controlled by politics—was
akin to the philosopher of science Otto Neurath’s analogy
that likened scientific verification to the reconstruction of a boat already at
sea:
We are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct
their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom. Where a beam is
taken away a new one must at once be put there, and for this the rest of the
ship is used as support. In this way…the ship can be shaped entirely anew, but
only by gradual reconstruction.
Any of the ship’s beams could be
moved—just as most any aspect of the Constitution could become a source of controversy.
But not all of the beams could be moved at once. Those that needed to stay in
place, at any one time, would comprise the Constitution that was agreed upon,
the foundation upon which constitutional debate could take place. That would
suggest that the Constitution was not neatly carved up between its hardwired, settled
features and its ambiguous, uncertain ones; rather, that activity of
constitutional sorting—in which certain things were debated while others were
necessarily conceded—was itself a fluid and historical practice, shifting as
constitutional politics themselves evolved. Perhaps the image of Neurath’s boat
helps us better understand how, from a historical perspective, during the first
half century of its existence the Constitution could both be a source of
irreconcilable debate and yet do so much to shape and control that very debate.
Often,
more effort is spent trying to establish how the Constitution ought to be
understood rather than how its authority has been instantiated in practice. Carefully
charting the Constitution’s historical development, as The Partisan Republic
does so well, can help answer this need. The book’s invigorating account of early
constitutional conflict and change not only offers a splendid overview of a vital
subject during a formative period of its development but helps show just how
much can be learned about the Constitution if its history is reconstructed with
rigor and care.
Jonathan
Gienapp is Assistant Professor of History at Stanford University. He can be
reached at jgienapp@stanford.edu.
Posted 9:30 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |