E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
In
her provocative new book, The Cult of the Constitution, Mary Anne Franks
skillfully weaves together liberal and conservative strands of constitutional fundamentalism,
focusing in particular on the First and Second Amendments. To preserve their own
power and privilege, “constitutional fundamentalists focus on individual rights
of speech and bearing arms while disregarding the equal protection guarantees
of the Fourteenth Amendment.” (p. xii) In the process, Franks diagnoses: “As
Second Amendment Fundamentalists have done with the right to bear arms, First
Amendment fundamentalists have transformed the right to free speech into a
superright with no sensitivity to context or to corresponding
responsibilities.” (p. 116)
This
diagnosis has concrete doctrinal implications. In an example Franks mentions in
passing, the story of Second Amendment fundamentalism plays out in a case
involving the First Amendment: “Not only does the fundamentalist interpretation
of the right to bear arms increasingly undermine the right to free
speech—Second Amendment fundamentalists have attempted to prevent physicians
from asking patients questions relating to firearms,” (p. 44) and “Second
Amendment fundamentalism has served as a justification for varied attempts to
literally stifle speech” including “preventing physicians from asking about
guns in the home.”(p. 102) I want to
spend a little more time on this case, Wollschlaeger v. Florida (popularly also known as Docs v.
Glocks), to highlight the doctrinal implications of what Franks calls the
fundamentalist approach to the First Amendment. Professional speech usefully illustrates
aspects of this phenomenon, particularly the reflexive incorporation of several
doctrinal features into all areas of speech, regardless of context and without much
deliberation as to its theoretical soundness.
Florida’s
Firearms Owners’ Protection Act (FOPA) was enacted in 2011 ostensibly to address
anecdotal evidence of patients (or minor patients’ parents) taking offense at
physicians’ customary questions about gun ownership. In fact, the relevant
professional groups, including the American Medical Association, recommend inquiring
about gun ownership as a matter of course. Nonetheless, the opinion recounts as
one of six instances motivating the Florida legislature to enact FOPA that an NRA
representative not only reported a physician’s refusal to treat a child if the
parent didn’t answer the gun question but also “testified at a subcommittee
hearing that ‘[q]uestioning parents about gun ownership to satisfy a political
agenda . . . needs to stop.’” But the Eleventh Circuit struck down FOPA because
it impermissibly imposed speaker-focused and content-based restrictions by limiting
doctors’ speech about gun ownership.
It
might appear that in this decision, the First Amendment prevented a fundamentalist
interpretation of the Second Amendment. But a closer look reveals that the
court’s First Amendment interpretation is itself based on what Franks may
identify as a fundamentalist understanding.
The
court struck down the Florida law because it violated the First Amendment’s
command of content neutrality. Since the Supreme Court’s decision in Reed v. Town of Gilbert, an aggressively expansive understanding
of content neutrality, in turn, has become one of the pillars of the modern deregulatory interpretation of the First Amendment. I’ve called
this purported extension of content neutrality to all areas of speech “the content-neutrality trap.” But in the context of
professional speech, content neutrality makes little sense. Indeed, the value
of professional speech to the client or patient lies precisely in its content. Moreover,
a professional’s speech within the professional-client or doctor-patient
relationship for the purpose of giving professional advice is constrained by
the imposition of malpractice liability for bad advice and by fiduciary duties.
Approaching professional speech from the premise of content neutrality,
however, misses these aspects. In other words, extending the requirement of
content neutrality to professional speech bears the hallmarks of First
Amendment fundamentalism Franks identifies: “no sensitivity to context or to
corresponding responsibilities.” Thus, reaching the correct result on shaky
reasoning, Docs v. Glocks offers a vivid illustration of acontextual and
reflexive contemporary First Amendment jurisprudence.
On
the surface, professional speech is merely in doctrinal disarray. The federal
appellate courts are divided on the First Amendment implications of speech that
occurs within the professional-client relationship, and the Supreme Court’s
recent decision in NIFLA
v. Becerra offers
only limited guidance. Yet, as I’ve explained elsewhere, “[m]uch of
professional speech doctrine in the courts has . . . developed around
conversion therapy laws and legislation concerning reproductive rights. Because
these issues remain contested, the development of professional speech doctrine
in the courts has been uneven and still lacks a coherent theoretical basis.” So
take a step back from Docs v. Glocks and the picture that emerges supports the
finding that those who have been affected by First Amendment fundamentalism in
this area are “those whose rights have been excluded, ignored, and
subordinated.” (p. 204)
Claudia
E. Haupt is an Associate Professor of Law and Political Science at Northeastern
University. You can reach her by e-mail at c.haupt at northeastern.edu