A Tale of Two Cities: Mary Anne Franks’s The Cult of the Constitution
Guest Blogger
For the Symposium on Mary Anne Franks,
The Cult of the Constitution (Stanford University Press, 2019).
Leslie Kendrick
Mary Anne Franks’s
The Cult of the Constitution opens
on August 11-12, 2017, in Charlottesville, Virginia, where I live with my
family. Franks’s project is to expose the harms caused by our society’s dual commitments
to the First and Second Amendments, and little illustrates those harms so well
as the two days when hundreds of white supremacists from
at
least 39 states converged on Charlottesville, where various of them
surrounded
and threw lit torches at student counterprotesters,
fired
a gun into a crowd,
beat
a beloved local elementary school aide in a parking garage,
injured
dozens of people, and
murdered
Heather Heyer.
Guns and speech are not the main story of August 11-12, 2017.
That story begins and ends with white supremacy, and focus on other elements
must not detract from that. Nevertheless, guns and free speech played important
roles. Guns were everywhere on August 12, and
their
relationship to First Amendment activity was everywhere in commentary after
the fact. The white supremacist violence recalled that of the Ku Klux Klan of a
century ago, now overlaid with 21
st century paramilitary weaponry. Groups
carrying assault rifles and wearing militia gear were virtually indistinguishable
from the National Guard. In the immediate aftermath, Gov. Terry McAuliffe
said
the white supremacists “had better equipment than our State Police had.”
Meanwhile, free speech jurisprudence that has been fairly
stable for a half century cannot by itself explain why hundreds of Americans in
2017 would march under Confederate and Nazi symbols chanting white supremacist
slogans. Yet our free speech practices facilitated this. Most materially, in
the days before the event, the City of Charlottesville attempted to shift the
rally out of the crowded downtown area to a larger park, but the move was
blocked
by a federal judge after the rally organizer brought suit with representation
from the Virginia ACLU. (After the mass violence of August 12, that
representation decision became a matter of national reckoning and ultimately
policy change by the ACLU: by August 18, the executive director had
announced
that the ACLU would no longer represent speakers seeking to demonstrate with loaded
weapons.) Our free speech law is not the only cause of what happened in
Charlottesville, but it is one.
Speaking of the role of guns and speech in August 11-12,
Franks concludes, “Charlottesville is who we are.” She goes on to observe,
however, that it is “not all we are.” To illustrate this, she turns to what is,
to me, another Charlottesville story. She turns to Khizr Khan, the
Muslim-American lawyer and Gold Star father—and Charlottesville resident—who
spoke at the 2016 Democratic convention. Mr. Khan and his wife Ghazala lost
their son,
Captain
Humayun Khan, a 27-year old University of Virginia graduate who dreamed of
becoming a military lawyer, when he was killed by an IED during Operation Iraqi
Freedom. At the convention, addressing the man who would eventually become president,
Mr. Khan
said,
“Let me ask you: Have you even read the U.S. Constitution? I will gladly lend
you my copy. In this document, look for the words ‘liberty’ and ‘equal protection
of law.’” For Franks, Khan’s stance and his words represent our societal commitment
to equality.
Franks argues that our commitments to guns and free speech
are in grave tension with our commitment to equality. Through three chapters
that make up the heart of the book, Franks argues that that robust
implementation of the First and Second Amendment causes harm—and not evenly
distributed harm, but harm that falls disproportionately on the marginalized.
In the context of guns, harms fall on women and nonwhite men who are victims of
gun violence while not being treated as beneficiaries of Second Amendment
protections. (Franks at 89). In the context of speech, “the primary targets of
silencing speech—harassment, threats, genocidal rhetoric, hate speech, revenge
porn—are women, nonwhite men, and sexual minorities.” (Franks at 116). Franks
focuses particularly on advocacy groups such as the NRA and the ACLU and argues
that such groups advocate for First and Second Amendment rights in more robust
terms than either right actually warrants. The result is an implementation of
liberty that undermines equality.
Franks advocates an “honest constitutional accounting” and a
constitutional culture that focuses on “those who have suffered the most severe
constitutional deprivations” (203). How does this look? “It looks like the
rejection of selective fidelity to constitutional rights. It looks like denying
attention to those who claim to honor the right to bear arms but look the other
way when black men are shot dead for exercising them. It looks like demanding
that those who defend the right of free speech respond to the silencing of
women” (203-4).
Franks provides vital attention to the disparate impact of
our First and Second Amendment commitments on marginalized groups. As I’ve
said
in another context, free speech is not free, and we do not split the check
evenly. The costs of our commitments should not be minimized or sanitized, and
Franks does necessary work in exposing them.
I am curious for more details on Franks’s constitutional
accounting. There are
various
ongoing
conversations
about the relationship between the First Amendment and equality, and more from
Franks would enrich this picture. Franks brings to her endeavor a powerful
combination of clear-eyed realism and unflagging advocacy for something better.
These skills, I would argue, contributed to the
drafting of the
first model criminal statute on revenge porn and its adoption by multiple
states. Given her extensive experience with legal reform, what particular changes
would she advocate and prioritize? And how much should be driven by pragmatics
and concerns about governmental abuse? Concerns about the likely tendencies of democratic
majorities are a large part of why we have the speech jurisprudence we do,
including, for instance, Justice Thurgood Marshall
arguing
that government neutrality toward ideas is an outgrowth of the Equal Protection
Clause. These questions do not admit of easy answers, but any answer of Franks
would be incisive and thought provoking.
I am also curious about Franks’s view of Fred Schauer’s
argument
in
Uncoupling Free Speech that we are wrong to conclude that “because a
price must be paid for free speech, it must be the victims of harmful speech
who are to pay it” (Schauer, Uncoupling Free Speech, 92 Columbia L. Rev. 1321,
1322 (1992).) Schauer urged more consideration of the uneven distribution of
the harms of free speech, and he proposed a thought experiment. What if,
instead of telling defamation victims they are out of luck, we compensated them
from a victims’ fund, collected from the public? The media would not bear a
cost that might chill protected speech, and the victims would receive compensation
for their injury. Schauer raised the possibility of the same approach for other
speech-related harms, including those caused by hate speech and pornography. I
am interested in what Franks would say.
My questions here have mostly been about what steps Franks
recommends in response to the problems she sees. The fact remains, however,
that simply by discussing the costs of our constitutional commitments, she is furthering
vital conversation.
Because know it or not, like Mr. Khan and me, we are all
living in Charlottesville.
Leslie Kedrick is Vice-Dean and David H. Ibbeken '71 Research Professor of Law at the University of Virginia. You can reach her by e-mail at kendrick at law.virginia.edu
Posted
9:30 AM
by Guest Blogger [link]