Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Judicial Norms and Judicial Capacity
|
Thursday, September 12, 2019
Judicial Norms and Judicial Capacity
Guest Blogger For the symposium on Andrew Coan, Rationing the Constitution: How Judicial Capacity Shapes Supreme Court Decision-Making (Harvard University Press 2019). Aziz Huq Andrew Coan is not just a terrific scholar—a quick perusal of “Rationing the Constitution” confirms that—he is also a pillar of the scholarly community in American constitutional law. As organizer of the only field-wide constitutional law event, held every winter in Tucson, he has innovated and thereby made a substantial contribution to the field. (I should disclose that he has twice invited me as commentator. I’ve profited much on both occasions from the debate and papers, but hope to ignore that generosity in the response that follows).
Coan’s design of the Tucson
conferences provides a useful counterpoint to the account of judicial review
offered in “Rationing the Constitution.” The first offers an ecumenical and
diverse perspective on many constitutional questions. The latter, called the
judicial capacity account, explains why we see the Court using only a small
part of “the constitutional choice set” (p.165), i.e., the set of all possible extrusions
of constitutional prohibitions and mandates via a selection among all potential
doctrinal specifications. On Coan’s reading, judicial constraint arises from the
Justices’ commitment to certain norms of professionalism, uniformity, and
“timely and efficient access” to adjudication (pp.14-16). These norms help
explain why the Court hews to clear, formal rules or deference to elected
institutions when doing otherwise invites either “high volume” or “high stakes”
litigation (p.23). The ensuing account of constitutional review is causally
distinct from the legalist, attitudinal, and strategic models of judicial
behavior that dominate academic literature now.
A churlish reduction of Coan’s
thesis would be a simple tautology: “the Court does only what it can do.” The
account’s richness and utility, however, springs from its identification of norms respecting Supreme Court adjudication
as the source of constraint (p.158). It thus stands or falls on the extent that
these norms can do load-bearing analytic work. Although there is much that is
new, important, and valuable in Coan’s theory, I cannot shake qualms. Some
pertain to his account of when the Court experiences a capacity constraint. The
more querulous, though, dog his assumption that norms can do the needful explanatory
work.
I start with some comments about the
ways in which Coan suggests that adjudication of a discrete legal issue can
generate capacity ‘bite.’ He sketches two. The first is that it is of such high
volume that “no procedural recalibration or shifting of resources from other
areas could possibly stem the tide” (p.25) The second is that an issue is of
such high stakes that the Court “is much less willing to tolerate
disuniformity” such that the “significant demand” on the Court’s attention will
“very quickly produce a … bottleneck.” (p.29). Both these capacity-straining
dynamics hinge on the sheer numerosity
of cases that the Supreme Court faces. They exclude the possibility of
extrinsic forces as a check on judicial action.
To begin with, I am not sure
“high volume” and “high stakes” are separate categories. There is no “pure”
case, Coan notes, of the latter (p.29). In practice, he invariably stresses the
“enormous volume” of cases as a dispositive factor (p.110). Occam’s razor might
have been wielded here to good effect.
Yet the category of “high volume”
cases is also troubling. At first, Coan’s definition of “high volume” issues is
framed in terms of challenges to “government action … at all levels.”
(pp.25-26). But in subsequent chapters, he suggests that it is only litigation
involving federal legislative or
agency action falls within his bailiwick (see, e.g., pp.74, 108, 152-53). And in
either case, Coan seems resolutely focused on the Supreme Court alone, rather
than the volume of cases experienced by the federal judiciary as a whole.
I think Coan is best read to
embrace the latter, less capacious definition (although I cannot be sure, see
pp.25-26). To me, the most interesting question is why. Why, first, should we
think about capacity in terms of just the Supreme Court? As Marin Levy
documented in a 2013 article,
the Court’s opinions more often than not express “floodgates” concerns about
the federal judiciary as a whole, rather than just the Supreme Court. Why not
take the Court at its word? And then, why just federal laws and regulations? Why not also count conflicting rules
on the conduct of individual federal officials? Or federal statutes, including
“superstatutes”
that are more consequential and more often litigated than many constitutional
provisions (p.35)? Or the federal validity of conflicting state laws? Coan here
cannot rely on some textual commitment. The formal criteria for certiorari
review adumbrated in Supreme
Court Rule 10 underscore interjurisdictional conflict and “important
question[s] of federal law,” including disputes about statutory interpretation
and administrative law. It does not pick out the narrower category to which
Coan appeals.
I will return below to try to
answer those questions. Here, I think it’s sufficient to say that there’s more
to Coan’s terms “high volume” and “high status” than first meets the eye. Both
are doing normative labor beyond what their plain-spoken exteriors allow.
Before we get to those answers, a
second element of Coan’s account merits attention: This is the implication that
when the Court faces high volume or high stakes it will “feel strongly
constrained” (p.31) to either defer to the elected branches or else adopt some
sort of categorical rule. This means, on Coan’s view, that “the government will almost always win,
or that the application of the Court’s
test will almost always be readily predictable by judges and litigants”
(pp.39-40; emphasis in original). Notwithstanding the use of disjunctive in
that sentence, I read Coan to suggest that the Court is commonly “constrained”
in ways that generate the eponymous constitutional rationing. Indeed, the gist
of the book is that the footprint of judicial review will generally be quite
limited.
The problem here is that Coan’s
analysis does not necessarily point toward either a highly diluted
constitutional shadow, or a predictably predictable rule. Rather, his analytic model
is consistent with a powerful Court capable to dramatically reshaping the
landscape of federal law in unanticipated ways.
To begin with, there is no reason
why a capacity-derived constraint on the adoption of standards, and a felt
compulsion to use instead rules, reduces the shadow of constitutional
prohibitions. There is no reason, as Coan implicitly acknowledges later, that
the Court cannot adopt rules that slice ruthlessly across the existing federal
regulatory landscape (p.172). “No independent agencies.” “No administrative
adjudication.” “No federal rule-making with force of law.” Such big things, as
T.E. Lawrence famously said (at least per David Lean), can have small
beginnings. The Court, I think, is perfectly capable of using crisp rules to
generate sweeping effects.
Nor are rules necessarily
predictable or tractable in the manner that Coan assumes. Just reflect on two
of Coan’s leading examples of stable and predictable categorical rules: the
economic/noneconomic distinction of Lopez and the activity/inactivity of Sebelius. I teach Lopez
a few hundred feet from where Gary Becker’s Nobel medal is kept. Becker won
for “[e]xtend[ing] the
domain of economic theory to aspects of human behavior which had previously
been dealt with by other social science disciplines such as sociology,
demography and criminology.” Whatever one thinks of its merits, that body of
work—and the enormous body of scholarship in its wake—complicate the
economic/noneconomic distinction. Nor is it at all clear why the Sebelius rule “threatened only one
existing federal statute.” (p.73). Students of federal power well recall that
the sin of Ollie’s Barbeque was one of omission—inactivity in the market of
African-American customers. If these rules have proved infertile berths for
follow-on litigation. it has nothing to do with their verbal formulation as
rules. (Readers of the Hart/Fuller debate will need no persuasion on that score).
Coan’s effort to derive a steady-state equilibrium from the juridical dominance
of rules, therefore, is unfounded. Something else entirely is needed to explain
why the floodgates don’t open.
Neither the conditions nor the consequences of constrained
judicial capacity in Coan’s theory, then, is as clear as he suggests. But these
concerns are ultimately ancillary to a deeper problem with the theory—a problem
that goes to the very heart of its contribution.
The causal motor of Coan’s
theory, recall, are a set of norms associated with Supreme Court adjudication. Coan
himself says, in an uncharacteristically ungainly turn of phrase, that “What
the judicial capacity model adds is the insight that judicial norms are crucial
to understanding the constraining force of judicial capacity” (p.158) At the
same time, he also recognizes but “bracket[s]” the possibility that his
load-bearing norms have “structural determinants.” (p.17). But I do not think
this is a plausible demarcation of analytic scope, and I do not believe that an
account of judicial behavior that relies on “norms” alone as its foundation can
fully avoid a measure of dubious circularity.
A first reason for concern is
that invoking “norms” as causal determinants of judicial behavior allows for
many degrees of freedom: In the absence of any determinate fixation of what
those norms entail, an analyst can simply look at the behavior to be explained,
and then reason back to a norm explanans. As I hinted above, Coan invites this
kind of criticism when he embeds key terms such as “high volume” and “high
stakes” with hidden assumptions about which
caseload matters, and what kinds of
disputes are important. The risk here is that “norms” are being derived
here simply by reasoning back from observed behavior. It is hard to see how
this procedure—which allows for the derivation of norms to predict behavior
from that very behavior—can be a basis for strong causal claims.
An additional problem is that
some of the specific norms that Coan cites are not, in fact, characteristic of
the federal legal system. He cites, for instance, a norm of “timely and
efficient access to the legal system” (p.16). This norm is certainly not
observed in important federal contexts, such as immigration
law. Perhaps the norm remains as aspiration, even as it is traduced on the
ground. If so, Coan ought to give us some reason to continue to make it
seriously as a normative commitment.
Finally, reliance on norms as a
source of capacity constraint begs the question of why those norms do not
buckle in the face of contrary felt compulsions. The current constitutional
dogfights over Brexit in the United Kingdom have nicely illustrated how
longstanding and seemingly inviolable norms can prove suddenly diaphanous. One
of the pressing and fascinating questions
at the time of this writing (early August 2019), indeed, is what constitutional
conventions persist in respect to parliament-executive relations. Conventions
in the U.K., as such norms are known in British constitutional parlance, have
long been thought more durable than their analogs in American law. Yet they
buckled there. And if not there, why not here,
especially since none of the norms upon which Coan relies are memorialized in
text or judicial precedent? Even setting to one side questions of content,
therefore, it is not sufficient to invoke the fact of a convention. It is also
necessary to offer an account of why the convention is stable and why it will
persist in the teeth of countervailing pressure to ends-oriented violation.
None of this is to say that the
judicial capacity model ought to be abandoned. To the contrary, I think that Coan
makes a useful start on clarifying the proper role of norms in an account of
judicial behavior, especially when he recognizes the potential endogeneity of
the judicial capacity model to alternative legal and strategic accounts, and
vice versa (pp.48-49). But in my view more needs to be said about the way in
which norms are specified and theirs causal predicates for the judicial
capacity model to ultimately endure. I hope that “Rationing the Constitution”
works as a useful first step to that larger project, a project that Andrew Coan
is eminently well-qualified to pursue.
Aziz Huq is the Frank and Bernice J. Greenberg Professor of Law at
University of Chicago Law School, and a visiting professor at Stanford Law
School. You can reach him by e-mail at huq at uchicago.edu
Posted 9:00 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |