Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The Bill of Rights and Social Contract Theory
|
Thursday, April 13, 2017
The Bill of Rights and Social Contract Theory
Guest Blogger Jud Campbell For the Symposium on Michael Klarman, The Framers' Coup: The Making of the United States Constitution.
Professor Klarman has written another wonderful book—this
time an extensive survey of the American Founding. The Framers’ Coup: The Making of the United States Constitution provides
readers with a vivid sense not only of the political and ideological divisions of
the era but also the Founders’ economic and social concerns, their personal
alliances and rivalries, and their many flaws. A great strength of the book is
Klarman’s decision to let historical figures speak for themselves, though his organization
and analysis make the book accessible to a wide audience. I highly recommend
it.
For my symposium contribution, I’ll focus on Klarman’s
chapter on the Bill of Rights. Overall, it’s super—especially by emphasizing the
prevalent attitude that the proposed amendments were inconsequential. Too much
written on this topic is hagiographic, reading our modern glorification of the
first ten amendments back onto the Founders.
Where I part with Klarman (among many others) is my view that
engaging with social-contract theory is essential for comprehending
Founding-Era debates about rights. This is a theme that I’m developing in other
work, but here I’ll illustrate the point by defending a prominent Federalist argument
that Klarman calls “hard to fathom”—namely, that amendments were unnecessary
because state declarations of rights
could constrain national power. My
broader point, and one with which Klarman seems to agree, is that the Founders
often thought very differently than we do about constitutional rights.
The basic history of the Bill of Rights will be familiar to
many readers. The Constitution originally included only a few rights, like the
criminal jury right in Article III, but failed to mention plenty of well-established
others, like the free exercise of religion, the freedom of the press, and the
civil jury right. And the enumeration of only some rights, Anti-Federalists warned,
left these others particularly vulnerable. A more complete declaration of
rights, they argued, should precede ratification.
Anti-Federalists didn’t quite prevail. But as various state
conventions ratified the Constitution, some of them qualified their approvals
by mentioning certain rights, like the freedoms of press and religion, while
others (or minorities within those conventions) made proposals for amendments.
For the most part, these proposals fell on deaf ears in the
Federalist-dominated First Congress. With great perseverance, however, James
Madison held Federalists’ feet to the fire, ultimately obtaining a variety of
constitutional amendments. But by then, Klarman points out, Anti-Federalists themselves
had cooled on the prospect of enumerating individual rights. What they really wanted were structural reforms and the
calling of another constitutional convention.
But why did so many Founders agree, at least after
ratification, that the proposed amendments were “of little or no consequence,”
as Lambert Cadwalader of New Jersey put it? Indeed, even Madison—the champion
of amendments in 1789—had derided declarations of rights as mere “parchment
barriers” just the year before.
Klarman provides a partial response, but the remainder of this
essay fleshes out another explanation for the befuddling yet widespread
indifference to Madison’s rights-enumerating project.
Today Americans typically think about constitutional rights
as being created by the Constitution. In order to enjoy the protection of these
rights, therefore, it is necessary to include them in the Constitution—usually
explicitly, as with the rights of free exercise, free speech, and so forth, but
sometimes implicitly, as with “substantive due process” rights. Either way, though,
the ultimate source of constitutional rights is the Constitution itself.
But lots of Founders simply didn’t think that way. And a
principal reason why was their immersion in a constitutional theory that we mostly
relegate to political-science and philosophy departments: social-contract
theory.
In essence, social-contract theory was a backward-looking
thought experiment designed to justify, and to limit, governmental authority.
The basic idea was straightforward. In order to understand the proper role of
government, we can imagine a situation in which no government existed and then
reconstruct the basic terms under which individuals would have unanimously
agreed (in a “social contract”) to join together to form a political society—a
body politic known as “the people.” Only after
everyone had reached this unanimous agreement would the people then, under
majority rule, form a system of government in a constitution.
Social-contract theory was ubiquitous in Founding-Era
constitutional thought, even if sometimes hidden in plain sight. The very first
sentence of the Constitution, for instance, is written in the language of social-contract
theory. “In the Preamble,” William Findley of Pennsylvania recognized during
the ratification controversy, “it is said, ‘We
the People,’ and not ‘We the States,’
which therefore is a compact between individuals entering into society, and not
between separate states enjoying independent power and delegating a portion of
that power for their common benefit.”
The Founders widely thought that individuals entering into a
social contract would have agreed that the body politic had to preserve natural
liberty—the freedom that humans would enjoy in an imagined state of nature—and
had to guarantee certain positive rights—“the equivalent every man receives, as
a consideration for the rights he has surrendered,” as Theophilus Parsons described.
These positive rights were rules about what the government had to do, like provide for trial by jury, and what the government could not do, like impose cruel and
unusual punishments. Consequently, as Thomas Jefferson explained, rights
included not only “unceded portions of right”—that is natural rights, like “freedom of religion”—but
“but also “certain fences which experience has proved peculiarly efficacious
against wrong, and rarely obstructive of right,” like “trial by jury, Habeas
corpus laws, [and] free presses.”
And this is where we return to Founding-Era indifference about
enumerating rights. For those who thought that individual rights were
guaranteed in the social contract, it was unnecessary to enumerate them in a
Constitution or declaration of rights. The rights already existed. That did not
mean that declaring rights was worthless; enumeration, for instance, might facilitate
the political and judicial defense of rights. But crucially, as historians have
broadly recognized, enumeration was mostly a declaratory exercise. “A Bill of Rights,” George Nicholas explained
at the ratification convention in Virginia, “is only an acknowledgement of the
pre-existing claim to rights in the people. They belong to us as much as if
they had been inserted in the Constitution.” The Ninth Amendment, with its
reference to “other[ rights] retained by the people,” reflects the same idea.
In light of these principles, the Federalist denials of a
need for a bill of rights made a good deal of sense. Klarman’s criticism of
Roger Sherman’s dismissive attitude about enumerated federal rights thus misses the mark. “The state Declarations of
Rights are not repealed by this Constitution, and being in force are
sufficient,” Sherman insisted toward the end of the deliberations. “This was a
surprising weak argument,” Klarman announces, adding that it is “hard to
fathom” how state declarations of rights would offer any protection against
federal abuses in light of the Supremacy Clause.
If we return to social-contract theory, however, Sherman’s
argument makes a good deal of sense. The original source of political authority,
after all, was the (imagined) unanimous consent
of the people to the social contract. This is what James Wilson was talking
about when he wrote, “The sovereign, when traced to his source, must be found
in the man.” Unlike state bodies
politic, however, the federal body politic
was about to be formed through a delegation of sovereignty from state bodies
politic, not through the presumed agreement of each and every individual. “[W]e
are not working on the natural rights of men not yet gathered into society,”
Edmund Randolph explained during the Convention, “but upon those rights,
modified by society.” And this reveals why Sherman disclaimed any need for a
federal bill of rights. State bodies politic obviously could not delegate authority to abridge individual rights
when they themselves lacked authority to abridge those rights. The rights
belonged to individuals, and state bodies politic could not give them away.
Plenty of other Federalists drew on social-contract theory
to make the same argument. Individual rights were “already provided for by the State Constitutions,” Tench Coxe
insisted, “and relating only to personal
rights, they could not be mentioned in a
contract among sovereign states.” Importantly, Coxe was not denying federal
sovereignty by adopting the proto-Confederate position that the Constitution
was simply a glorified treaty—a “compact under the style & title of a Constitution,”
as Thomas Jefferson infamously declared in 1798. Rather, Coxe was restating the
standard Federalist position that the Constitution would form a national body
politic through a delegation of
sovereignty rather than through an original social contract among
individuals.
To be sure, Anti-Federalists had reasonable arguments on the
other side. “This system, if it is possible for the people of America to accede
to it, will be an original compact,” Brutus remarked, “and being the last,
will, in the nature of things, vacate every former agreement inconsistent with
it.” Or, as Federal Farmer put it, “The bills of rights, and the state
constitutions, are fundamental compacts only between those who govern, and the
people of the same state,” whereas if “the people of the United States make a
federal constitution, which is a fundamental compact between them and their
federal rulers,” then the federal government “cannot be bound to take notice of
any other compact.” Indeed, if state declarations of rights truly limited
federal power, Federal Farmer observed, then why had the Convention mentioned
rights like habeas corpus and the criminal jury right?
In any event, my goal here is not to take historical sides.
Rather, what I hope to have illustrated is the central importance of
social-contract theory for comprehending Founding-Era debates about rights. And
this, it seems to me, reinforces a central theme of Klarman’s book: Though we
often feel a deep intergenerational connection to the Founders, these men had their
own goals and interests, their own flaws, and their own ways of thinking. Indeed,
those who wish to know the Founders better should read Klarman’s book.
Jud Campbell is Assistant Professor of Law at the University of Richmond School of Law. You can reach him by e-mail at jcampbe4 at richmond.edu
Posted 9:00 AM by Guest Blogger [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |