E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Four days ago, I posted
in this space some reflections about a very good conference I’d just
attended at the University of San Diego Law School’s Center for the Study of
Originalism.The core of my reflection
concerned a hypothesis I developed over the course of the conference: that there
has been some movement in recent years among leading originalists toward the
view that originalism hasn’t yet really been tried out in American courts.Holding in abeyance the question of whether
that hypothesis is correct—I didn’t do a survey of the thirty or so
originalists at the conference, and I wouldn’t know how representative that
group of thirty is of academic originalists overall—I then offered some
thoughts about what would be interesting about movement toward that perspective
among originalist theorists.
I’ve gotten various feedback to that post: some agreeing,
some criticizing, some speculating further.But one note of feedback seems to me to be worth reporting to the
audience for these posts.After my first
post, two or three originalists who had attended the conference got in touch
with me to let me know that they, personally, do not subscribe to the
originalism-has-never-been-tried view, and one or two of them ventured further
that they think I overestimated the number of people at the conference who do.In a more
recent post, John McGinnis—one of the prominent originalists at the
conference I attended—has also come forth to say that I overestimated the
incidence of the never-been-tried idea.Given this feedback, I should take seriously the possibility that I did
in fact overestimate.
It’s certainly possible.I heard the idea articulated, in a few different forms, by (I think) five
people at the conference.But given the
perceptions of others who were there, it’s possible that I overread the
significance of that observation, in any of the following ways: (1) I extrapolated
from what I heard, figuring that the people I heard from probably weren’t the
only people at the conference to hold forms of that view.But maybe I overextrapolated; maybe I
happened to hear from everyone, or close to everyone, who has something like
that perspective. (2) Maybe the originalists who report that the position is
not on the rise are working from a different (and perhaps better informed) baseline
than I am.Maybe people who attend
originalism conferences regularly were already accustomed to whatever the
incidence of this idea is among originalists, and I saw as an uptick what to
them is simply the status quo.And then
of course there are questions about the ability of insiders and outsiders to
read a culture.Sometimes insiders can
better read what is actually going on in a community; sometimes it takes an
outsider to notice something that insiders haven’t.Which of those dynamics was more in play in
this case, if either, isn’t something I’m qualified to judge.But in any event, I’m grateful to those who
reached out with the feedback, which should (and does) induce in me a healthy skepticism
about my hypothesis of an uptick.
Of greater interest to a general audience than my
perceptions, though, is the underlying set of issues about the ways in which
originalism is old, new, or some combination of both.To a considerable degree, I agree
with McGinnis when he says that the practice of arguing from original
meanings has waxed and waned over the course of American history and that it is
today one of several contending approaches to constitutional jurisprudence,
rather than being either alien or dominant.I certainly agree that anyone who thinks American judges have never reasoned
about constitutional cases by appealing to original meanings would be misreading
the historical record, and not by just a little.
Where I may differ from McGinnis is in certain judgments about
how predominant originalism was at specific past times.Quoting Madison and also Howard Gillman,
McGinnis identifies originalism as present at the Founding and asserts that
nearly all constitutional interpreters appealed to original meanings until the
time of the twentieth-century progressives.McGinnis is right, of course, that Madison and Gillman said what he says
they said.I have great respect for
Gillman—and not less for Madison.But I
have always thought that Gillman overstated the case for universal originalism
in the nineteenth century.(Paul Kahn’s Legitimacy
and History still stands as one powerful contrary view.)And Madison’s endorsement of a jurisprudence of
original meanings in the passage McGinnis quotes stands in contrast to some
ideas articulated by his contemporaries.Madison is called the Father of the Constitution, as McGinnis reminds us—but
Gouverneur Morris, who actually wrote more of the document than any other
single person, famously derided the idea, saying with the authority of the man
who held the pen that a history of the Constitution would not be a good aid in
interpreting its provisions. (To be clear, McGinnis doesn't say that everyone was an originalist near the Founding, just as I am not saying that no one was.)
The point here is not that people didn’t reason from and
about original meanings near the time of the Founding.Of course they did—which means “of course
many of them did, at least some of the time.”And others of them were skeptical of that approach.Similarly, one can find originalist reasoning
cropping up in many nineteenth- and twentieth-century sources, which doesn’t
demonstrate that originalism, much less any particular form of originalism, was
the consensus or dominant method of that age.Argument from original meanings, it seems to be, have always been one
strain of constitutional arguments, jostling with several other strains—a state
of affairs that is still true today and that I would bet is likely to continue
for some time.