E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Musing
as I do on occasion about the legal academics who have most influenced my way
of thinking about law, Jan Deutsch is one of the top three. I can’t say that I
was a “student” of Deutsch; I took one class and one seminar from him. The
class was Corporations, and all I remember from it are two episodes. In the
first he engaged in a sustained line of questioning of my classmate Richard
Diamond, at the end of which he asked, “So, now, Mr. Diamond, do you see your
behind in front of you?” – a pointed way of saying that he had managed to get
Richard to answer one question, then another, then another, to the point where
his final answer contradicted the one he originally gave.[1]
I can’t fully reconstruct the second incident, but its thrust was that in
making a corporate deal we would react differently were we told to meet a
lawyer with responsibility for the deal on a street corner where he’d be
wearing a trench coat or told instead to go to the offices of Jones, Day (a law
firm at which Deutsch had worked) and meet the lawyer there. I now understand
the point of the observation to be that law is backed up by a set of social
expectations that are never fully captured in the formal law – something of a
“law and society” observation – but I can’t say that I understood it that way
then.
The
seminar was a different matter, and it is one of three encounters with
Deutsch’s thought that decisively shaped the way I think about law. The seminar
was “Law and Psychiatry,” and it was usually co-taught by Professors Joseph Goldstein
and Jay Katz. It was a “hot ticket” when I was at Yale, because Professor
Goldstein had an “in” with Judge David Bazelon of the Court of Appeals for the
District of Columbia Circuit, and Judge Bazelon was what we’ve now come to call
a feeder judge to the Supreme Court’s liberal justices. As a result, ambitious
Law Journal editors competed for seats in the seminar. I took the seminar
because, perhaps oddly, I was actually interested in the subject. My family was
quite psychoanalytically oriented: An uncle was an influential figure in the
Los Angeles psychoanalytic community, and my older sister and her husband were
both analysts. And, as it happened, Professor Goldstein was on leave that
semester, and Deutsch taught the seminar with Professor Katz.
At
some point in the seminar the light went on in my head. As I came to interpret
the conversations in the seminar, Professor Katz was defending the proposition
that the kinds of clinical judgments trained professionals reached embody a
distinctive – and perhaps ineffable – form of knowledge, and that those
clinical judgments were quite different from the kinds of rule-guided judgments
lawyers were trained to make. As the semester developed, I saw that Deutsch was
repeatedly making the point that rule-guided judgments were not in principle
different from clinical ones (or, to put the latter in terms more congenial to
lawyers, from all-things-considered judgments). I’m not sure that I would have
put it this way at the time, but Deutsch’s argument, as I came to assimilate
it, was that the equivalences ran both ways: A clinical judgment was just the
result of an accumulation of rule-guided judgments that could be teased out
through careful analysis, and the judgments reached in a system of complex
rules could never be fully justified by any identifiable subset of rules. In
some sense, I think, that was where I began to think about the so-called
indeterminacy thesis associated with critical legal studies (and before that,
with legal realism).
My
second encounter with Deutsch came in reading his article, “Precedent and
Adjudication,”[2]
which simply blew me away. I continue to recommend it to students as probably
the best article in constitutional law – ever. As I describe it, the article
consists of Deutsch’s almost literal dissection of a single Supreme Court
opinion. Its underlying structure, though not its surface, is this: Take the
opinion, rearrange its paragraphs, and you discover that the rearranged opinion
means something quite different from the original – even though the words in
the “two” opinions are exactly the same. The lesson to be drawn from the
article is a simple but I think quite deep one: What a decision said to be a
precedent means is determined not by the opinion itself but by what later
judges make of it. Or, a precedent is what later judges say it is. In that
sense, later judges can’t “distort” or “mangle” precedents – and, importantly,
they can’t be constrained by precedents either.[3]
My final encounter came
quite a bit later. At some point, probably while we were in law school, Duncan
Kennedy (the second in the array of legal academics who shaped my thinking)
communicated his enthusiasm about Deutsch’s article, “Neutrality, Legitimacy,
and the Supreme Court: Some Intersections Between Law and Political Science.”[4]
I read the article, but couldn’t see why Duncan was so enthusiastic about it.
Re-reading the article a few decades later, I did. Again, as I describe it, the
article is a complete deconstruction of Legal Process thinking, taking it
seriously on its own terms and exposing its internal contradictions. As I came
to see things (which is not to say, as things really were), Legal Process
scholars presented themselves as the sophisticated heirs to Legal Realism, but
without the reduction of law to politics that they associated with the most
hard-core Realists. True, they agreed, we were irreducibly divided over
questions of the substantive policies our polity should pursue but, they
contended, we could agree on a “principle of institutional settlement”
according to which we would assign authority to make substantive policy choices
to an array of institutions with distinctive characteristics. And, importantly,
the principle of institutional settlement was a-political, and so it sustained
the distinction between law and politics.[5]
Deutsch’s article accepts
the Legal Process premises at every point up to the principle of institutional
settlement. But, it shows, exactly the same reasons Legal Process scholars gave
for accepting the proposition that we could not come to an a-political
agreement on substantive policy were available – and were equally cogent – with
respect to the principle of institutional settlement. The distinction between
law and politics that Legal Process scholarship tried to reconstruct collapsed
once again.
All three encounters led
me to what I suppose some might think are banal insights. My experience in the
legal academy suggests otherwise. The idea that there is a real difference
between all-things-considered judgments and rule-guided ones is an important
theme in much contemporary scholarship, for example, and of course the effort
to sustain a distinction between law and politics continues with no less zeal
than ever before.
But, for me, Jan Deutsch
was there already.
[1] I’ve never been able to do that with
a student, and not, I think, because my students wouldn’t be as astute as
Richard in being able to provide answers to each question as it arose.
[5] Whether the best Legal Process
scholars thought that the principle of institutional settlement was indeed
a-political is unclear to me. I have in mind the stunning passage in Hart &
Sacks where the authors ask, about a specific choice among institutional
decision-makers, whether the Chamber of Commerce and the Soviet Politburo would
reach the same conclusion. I’m inclined to treat that as a genuine question on
the authors’ part, which could be given either answer. And, if the answer is
“No,” the implication is that the principle of institutional settlement is not
a-political.