E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
This paper focuses on the
crucial elements of post-Civil War constitutionalism scholars miss when they
give the place of pride to the Civil Rights Act at the expense of the Second
Freedmen’s Bureau Bill. The Republicans
who framed the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill understood that judicial action
could not eradicate slavery. Their
legislative and constitutional program recognized that persons could transition
from slaves to full citizens only if Congress aggressively exercised national
power under Section 2 of the Thirteenth Amendment. Legislation was necessary to provide former
slaves with various goods and services, the precise provision of which
depending on local circumstances and changing conditions. Given the need for a high degree of
nimbleness in the managing of that transition, entrenching crucial features of
the Freedmen’s Bureau Bill in a constitutional amendment that would be enforced
by the federal judiciary made little sense.
Instead, the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill was drafted by Republicans
who understood that Congress rather than the judiciary was expected to play the
lead role in removing all badges and incidents of slavery in American
constitutional life.
The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill was also designed to
prevent white persons from making transitions from freedom to dependency. Sections 3-6 of that bill provided both
freedmen and destitute refugees with various goods and services. Republican supporters of this provisions emphasized
that Congress had the obligation to act for the general welfare and that
preventing the dependency inherent in economic destitution justified
legislative action. As significantly,
Republicans were as inclined to justify the provision of goods and services to
white persons who had never been slaves under Section 2 of the Thirteenth
Amendment. Their arguments for the
constitutionality of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill insisted that a minimum
degree of economic security and education was a central condition of freedom
and full citizenship.
Restoring the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill to the core
of Reconstruction explains some features of the post-Civil War Amendments,
while challenging other shibboleths of American constitutionalism. Commentary on the post-Civil War Amendments
begins by acknowledging that the text speaks in generalities, but fails to
appreciate the institutional logic of that language. Republicans did not ratify a precise legal
code because they recognized that Congress needed substantial discretion to
determine the policies that best ensured that persons of color transitioned
from slavery to enjoying the full rights of citizens of a free republic and
not, as often maintained, because they could not agree on specifics or were more
interested in moral exhortation that precise legal norms. Contrary to Richard Posner and William
Rehnquist, the Constitution of the United States is not a charter of negative
liberties. The Second Freedmen’s Bureau
Bill’s Constitution is committed to ensuring the national government has the
power necessary to act for the general welfare and, as such, is more an
instrument for preventing local and private tyranny than for limiting
government. Reconstruction Republicans
believed that national government under the Thirteenth Amendment had duties to
provide goods and services to destitute citizens and freedmen who need
government assistance making the transition for slavery to independent
citizen. Finally, the debates over the
Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill highlight the perversity of contemporary
constitutional decisions which insist that the federal judiciary is the
institution primarily responsible for implementing the post-Civil War
amendments. Republicans when defending
the constitutionality of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill uniformly insisted
that Congress was the institution constitutionally charged with guaranteeing
those positive rights, not the Supreme Court of the United States. More precisely, the Republican Party had the
place of constitutional honor. The
post-Civil War Amendments were framed at a time when the dominant party were
considered the primary vehicle for ensuring constitutional fidelity. Republicans in the Thirty-Eighth Congress
assumed that their party, not any particular institution, was the institution
that determined the measures constitutionally necessary to realize the promise
of the Thirteenth and, later, Fourteenth Amendments. Their arguments on the Second
Freedmen’s Bureau Bill highlight the crucial features of American
constitutionalism that judges, governing officials, lawyers and citizens miss
when they look at the Constitution through the modern lens of judicial
supremacy.
The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill’s Constitution provides
a distinctive perspective on economic inequalities and American
constitutionalism. The persons
responsible for the original Constitution and post-Civil War Constitution were
concerned with economic inequalities or at least economic rights, but their
concerns are not explicitly manifested in the text of the Constitution. The Constitution of 1789 and the Constitution
of 1868 do not enumerate economic rights because their framers regarded
constitutions as empowering rather than as disabling mechanisms. Contemporary Americans assume that
constitutions protect rights by enumerating limits on government power and
empowering the national judiciary to enforce those restrictions. The persons responsible for the Constitution
of 1789 believed that rights were best protected by structuring government
institutions so that elite leaders would have the combination of interests,
values and capacities that would lead them to protect rights. The persons responsible for the post-Civil
War Constitution believed rights were best protected when the party of the
majority of the people who remained loyal during the Civil War controlled all
three branches of the national government.
The Republicans responsible for the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill and
the post-Civil War Constitution believed destitution and dependency were forms
of slavery that the national legislature was constitutionally obligated to
alleviate under the Thirteenth Amendment.
Once we understand the Republican commitment to economic rights and the
way in which the constitution promoted those rights, we can see how the
Constitution of 1868 in many ways was better structured to place economic
inequality and dependency at the core of American constitutionality than the
judicially driven constitutionalism of the present.