Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Originalism and the Ted Cruz Question
|
Sunday, January 17, 2016
Originalism and the Ted Cruz Question
Joseph Fishkin The attacks on Senator Ted Cruz’ qualifications to be President have left me a little depressed. The reasons are several. First there’s the creeping sense that what it takes today to catapult a constitutional argument onto the front burner of our national public discourse is basically to have that argument come out of the mouth of Donald Trump. Whatever this says about our constitutional politics, it can’t be good. Second, there’s the nagging fact that Senator Cruz, like President Obama, is not white. There are undoubtedly a variety of reasons why Cruz’ “natural born”-or-not status is now getting more searching scrutiny than, say, George Romney’s (which did get some scrutiny) or John McCain’s. But among those various reasons, it’s hard for me to believe Cruz’s race plays no role. Third, the debate about Cruz’ qualifications underscores the dispiriting prospect that birtherism or something resembling it may be a permanent feature of our politics going forward rather than a bizarre historical footnote to the Obama years. Permanent birtherism, like neverending 9/11 trutherism, Sandy Hook trutherism, and so on, seems to suggest some very deep well of paranoia in American politics. To be clear: I am not suggesting that people questioning Ted Cruz’ eligibility are either paranoid, racist, or supporters of Donald Trump—you, dear reader, may well be questioning his eligibility while sitting nowhere near that particular Venn diagram. My worries here are about why the meme of his possible ineligibility might be spreading so rapidly and widely. Anyway put all of this aside. What actually bothers me most about our current debate about Ted Cruz’ “natural born” status is what it says about how so many of us apparently choose to think about the Constitution—specifically, the way many of us seem to practice originalism, which is so often so much worse and less defensible in practice than in theory. To step back a moment, here’s how I think one ought to resolve the question of Ted Cruz’ eligibility to be President. First, let’s view the Constitution at an appropriately high level of abstraction to capture the conceptual heart of what this (totally morally indefensible) “natural born” distinction is about. At this level of abstraction, the Constitution suggests a simple dichotomy. Some U.S. citizens are “natural born.” Others are not—they are “naturaliz[ed]” later. Those are the only two categories (once those present at the founding have left the stage). All citizens, in other words, are “natural” one way or the other: some by being born, others through a later process appropriately called “naturalization.” As history has unfolded, Congress has made various rules not only about naturalization itself (an enumerated power under Art. I § 8 cl. 4) but also rules about who is a citizen at birth (an unenumerated power, very closely linked with that enumerated one, which it has exercised since 1790, when a statute provided that some children of U.S. citizens born abroad were to be deemed natural citizens at birth). Fast forward to 1970, when Ted Cruz is born. Assuming his mother was a U.S. citizen, and satisfied the relevant residency requirements under then-prevailing statutory law to make Ted Cruz a U.S. citizen at all, at birth, he then would also be a “natural born” citizen. The phrase just means, a citizen at birth. But wait! What about British common law, eighteenth-century British statutory law, the relationship of these two sources of law, Blackstone’s commentaries on either, the relation of “subject” to “citizen,” and what James Madison might have thought about any of it? Surely we need to debate a flotilla of obscure questions like this in order to decode the meaning of the “natural born” clause? No. In my view, we don’t need all that stuff. My view is compatible with a range of conceptions of what we are up to when we interpret the Constitution—not only a “common law” approach to interpretation but also an approach that prioritizes constitutional text, and even, as Jack suggests in his post, some kinds of originalism. (Originalism anywhere in the Balkin/Kagan ballpark, basically.) But then there’s another, sadly more familiar, kind of originalism—one that says what we absolutely must do is think about whether the original understanding (original public meaning, etc.) of the phrase “natural born citizen” would have encompassed the case of Ted Cruz. If that’s your approach, then you’re definitely off to the races with obscure eighteenth-century British statutes and their interaction with (or role in) the common law tradition as incorporated into American constitutionalism in 1789. But here’s the rub: if you go that way, you’re going to end up stuck in an interpretive rut anyway, and you’ll need modern jurisprudence to bail you out. Why? Because of sex. Those eighteenth-century British statutes contemplated citizenship as passing from fathers to children—only. In Cruz’s case, his dad was not an American in 1970, so the question is whether he can be a “natural born citizen” because of his mother. The eighteenth-century public meaning is surely that no, he can’t. As far as I know (admittedly, not far!) matrilineal passing of citizenship was not a thing in eighteenth-century Anglo-American law. So then should the rule be that even today, you’re a “natural born” citizen if you’re born in Canada with an American dad, but not if all you’ve got is an American mom? In other words, “Sorry Ted, but in 1789, citizenship came through fathers, not mothers, so you’re out of luck.” Obviously that is not going to be the rule. It’s too blatantly discriminatory and sexist. So, one would assume, the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause will come to the rescue and correct eighteenth-century originalist understandings of this point—surely the Fourteenth Amendment’s sex discrimination jurisprudence would not allow differential treatment of fathers and mothers for purposes of determining the citizenship of their children. This move is, of course, not originalist at all. But it’s one we have to hold our noses and make, to save our narrow originalist approach from the laughing-stock irrelevance to which it would fairly be consigned if we really tried to argue that it’s only American dads abroad, today, who can have “natural born” citizen children, and American moms can’t. Phew! Dodged a bullet there. Except… there is actually modern constitutional law on almost precisely this point, and according to a 5-4 majority led by Justice Kennedy in a controversial case, our law can and does, consistent with the U.S. Constitution, treat fathers and mothers very differently for purposes of conferring U.S. citizenship on their children born abroad. According to Nguyen v. INS, it does not violate the Fourteenth Amendment for Congress to legislate—as it has, shamefully, legislated—different and stricter rules for the children of American fathers born abroad than for those of American mothers born abroad, regarding who is a citizen and what you have to do to become a citizen later on. This twentieth-century distinction cuts in the opposite direction from the eighteenth-century one. Essentially, where the parents are unmarried, the law holds that children of American fathers need to formally establish paternity or get an acknowledgment of paternity or a promise of support, whereas children of American mothers do not need any of these things. Justice Kennedy held that real differences in how men and women are situated in relation to childbirth justifies this large difference in treatment. He denies that the law relies on stereotypes about men and women as parents (e.g. just for example, the stereotype that men are going around sowing their wild oats and producing many children they don’t really have relationships with, whereas women never do this). Ok. So would Nguyen, flipped around the other way, justify allowing eighteenth-century common law understandings of patrilineal descent to continue to determine the meaning of the “natural born citizen” clause in the twenty-first century despite their obviously sex-discriminatory character? Almost certainly not. But answering that question requires a deeply modern encounter with the anti-stereotyping jurisprudence of modern constitutional sex discrimination law—the entire edifice of which is one that the narrow kind of originalists who would be stuck pursuing this inquiry in the first place tend either to reject, or to hold their noses and grudgingly accept as a matter of stare decisis, that old crutch, and that’s it. My point is this. We have choices about how we go about interpreting the Constitution. We can look for meaning at levels of abstraction that yield principles applicable to the modern world—and then we can apply them to the modern world, in ways that take into account relevant inputs, such as modern federal statutes, that may color their specific operative meaning in a given context. That’s the approach I tried to follow above. It’s an approach (or really a family of different approaches) that neither ignores, nor fetishizes, constitutional text. We let 1789 have its say but not the last word. Or alternatively, we can try the approach of all too many originalists: to try our hardest to give 1789 the last word. We can look to a common law tradition that we pretend ends at 1789 (except when we can’t help ourselves, cf. the dates on Justice Scalia’s sources of original meaning in Heller). We can treat the original understanding as exceedingly specific and detailed, even though the higher the level of specificity and detail we seek, the more indeterminate the answer often becomes. Then once we’ve got our narrow-originalist answer, hermetically sealed off from contamination from modern understandings, we pull it out of cold storage and apply it to whatever our modern controversy may be. Except sometimes, for all that, the whole thing runs aground, as in the story I have just told, on some major modern cross-cutting constitutional provision that didn’t exist in 1789 anyway. And then what exactly have we achieved, other than a sort of apparently-pleasing aesthetic feeling that we’ve put lots of weight on the old and little on the new? We haven’t (in practice) gotten much in the way of determinate answers, constraints on judges, or the other supposed virtues of this type of approach. Perhaps someone can explain to me—since I don’t see it—why this narrow originalist approach is nonetheless the way to go. Maybe Ted Cruz? Posted 11:02 AM by Joseph Fishkin [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |