E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Tarunabh Khaitan’s valuable book, A
Theory of Discrimination Law, proposes a general account of a type of
law that now can be found in many countries.He proposes four conditions which are individually necessary and
cumulatively sufficient to make a norm of discrimination law: the norm should
have some connection with a ground that divides all persons between two or more
groups, at least one of whose members must be significantly more disadvantaged
in relation to members of another group defined by the same ground; and the
norm must be designed to distribute the direct substantive benefits or burdens
in question to some, but not all, members of a protected group.The book analytically disaggregates the
elements of antidiscrimination law thus defined.It also aims to specify the conditions under
which it makes sense for such a law to operate.The consequence is a work that is both analytic and normative.It is executed with admirable care.It convincingly establishes that this kind of
law is a transnational phenomenon with distinctive characteristics.
The book is impressive but somewhat frustrating.
Chapter Five is entitled “The Point of Discrimination Law.”That point, Khaitan thinks, is to make an
adequate range of valuable opportunities available to everyone.But he observes, as many commentators on
antidiscrimination law do not, that only some members of the protected group
benefit from the law.This point is worth
emphasizing.William Julius Wilson noted
long ago that both antidiscrimination law and racial preferences benefit the
black people who are best qualified, and so have been least injured by racism.(The Truly Disadvantaged 109-24 (1987).So the benefit to a limited number of people
must lead to some benefit to all the members of the group.
This benefit, Khaitan thinks, is a general elimination of
discriminatory behavior.“It is only the
cumulative effect of a critical mass of such [legal] actions, including the
deterrent effect of the threat of these actions and the internalization of the
antidiscrimination norm, which systematically connects the antidiscrimination
duty with its broader purpose of ameliorating relative group
disadvantage.”(192-93)If this broader purpose is understood, then
it is possible to dispel certain characteristically American confusions that
regard discrimination as an ordinary tort, like carelessly breaking someone’s
leg, and focusing exclusively on the intentions of the alleged
discriminator.The legitimacy of
antidiscrimination law depends on “its assumptions about a complex, dynamic,
and contested set of social facts.”(246)
This is a valuable corrective to the Supreme Court’s tendency,
noted long ago by Alan Freeman, to regard discrimination as merely "the
misguided conduct of particular actors" in "a world where, but for
the conduct of these misguided ones, the system of equality of opportunity
would work to provide a distribution of the good things in life without racial
disparities and where deprivations that did correlate with race would be
'deserved' by those deprived on grounds of insufficient 'merit.'"(Legitimizing
Racial Discrimination Through Antidiscrimination Law, 62 Minn. L. Rev.
1049, 1054 (1977).)The demand that any
civil rights claimant show that he is the individual victim of intentional
discrimination implies "that Black Americans can be without jobs, have
their children in all-black, poorly funded schools, have no opportunities for
decent housing, and have very little political power, without any violation of
antidiscrimination law."(1050)
Khaitan’s correction, however, does not answer Wilson’s concern.
Even if deterrence is perfect and
discrimination is eliminated – even if unconscious, discriminatory behavior is
eliminated - discrimination might not be the only reason why the group is
systematically disadvantaged.
In the contemporary United States, for example, discrimination
is certainly one reason why so many black Americans are poor and marginalized.But another is the continuing consequence of
a long history of marginalization, the social consequences of a punitive war on
drugs, and the disappearance of industrial jobs in the rust belt. The
consequence is a self-sustaining pattern of disadvantage that itself is a
powerful driver of racism.In obstetrics
wards on the south side of Chicago right now, there are newborn boys who, we
can feel confident, will commit stupid, pointless homicides in 16 years, and
others who will be the victims of those homicides.The high crime rate among African-Americans
itself reinforces old American tropes about black male dangerousness.Stopping discrimination won’t stop this from
happening.It would require intervention
on a massive and expensive scale, of a kind that the United States today shows
no interest in.(We don’t know enough
about what kinds of intervention would work, but we’re not investing much in
the way of resources to find out.)The
conditions Freeman described in 1977 are still with us.No clarification of or change in
antidiscrimination law is likely to fix it.
I argued, in my book Antidiscrimination
Law and Social Equality, that discrimination law only makes sense as part
of a larger project of changing cultural norms to eliminate such malign
ideologies as racism and sexism.Those
ideologies, and patterns of group disadvantage, form a self-sustaining cycle,
in which each reinforces the other.Discrimination
law can only be one element of the larger project of disrupting this cycle of
reproduction of a racist social reality.It can’t do the job itself. A
theory of medical care presupposes a theory of disease.
Khaitan acknowledges this. “The antidiscrimination duty, even
when effectively implemented, is likely to make but little impression upon
relative group disadvantage, and at best prevent its exacerbation. The reason
is simple. In order to make its imposition legitimate in a liberal state, the
duty had to be action-regarding and wrong-sensitive, and limited to a small set
of duty-bearers. ... Given these limitations, its impact on abiding, pervasive,
and substantial advantage gaps between groups is likely to be small. This does
not, of course, make the duty pointless. It plays an important role in seeking
to ensure that this advantage gap does not widen. Group dominance is
self-reinforcing. If the duty just manages to resist its expansionary
pressures, it would be successful. But that merely maintains the status quo,
which is freedom-inhibiting, even as it prevents it from worsening. Unraveling
relative group disadvantage will take more than successful internalization of
the antidiscrimination duty by its bearers. It calls for a good deal of
affirmative action.” (216-7) It is for this reason that he underscores the
“importance of acknowledging the conceptual and normative continuity not only
between the prohibition on direct and indirect discrimination but also between
this prohibition on the one hand and the provision for affirmative action on
the other.” (165)But of course
affirmative action won’t end relative group disadvantage either.
Khaitan notes at the end of his book that there might be,
outside his data set, “countries that have sought to address the problem of
relative group disadvantage through tools entirely distinct from (and, perhaps,
more effective than) discrimination law.”(249)This raises a serious
question about the point of discrimination law.It may be that discrimination law aims at remedying group disadvantage,
and does so, but less effectively than other tools.If this is so, than any defense is radically
incomplete.High fructose corn syrup is
a way of preventing death by starvation.The body must have glucose, but that is not a defense of high fructose
corn syrup, because there are other ways of preventing starvation and delivering
glucose that are far healthier.Sometimes
discrimination law is the right tool for the job.Sometimes it isn’t.A theory of discrimination law ought to be
able to tell us which is which.