E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
For the Symposium on Roberta Kwall, The Myth of the Cultural Jew
Professor Kwall pursues several
goals in her enlightening, informative, provocative and frustrating book. One
objective is to demonstrate that there is a human element to Jewish law. Both
internal Jewish culture and the foreign cultures in which Jews were embedded
for much of our history significantly influenced the changing substance of
Jewish law. This is Kwall’s strongest thesis and it is expertly developed. A
second goal is to demonstrate the utility of cultural analysis in understanding
Jewish law and culture. I leave that
discussion to others.
The third goal addresses the
question of whether Jewish particularity can survive if Jews define themselves
solely in cultural terms. If “cultural” Jews reject both the Jewish religion
and Jewish law, is there anything left that defines them distinctively as Jews
that will persevere and continue over time? Kwall’s answer to this question is
“No” and she fears what such an adaptation of Jewish identity would mean for
the future of the Jewish people, particularly in the United States.
Notwithstanding the title, this is the least developed discussion in her book.
I share Professor Kwall’s concerns about
the longevity of Jewish tradition if it is anchored to nothing more than a sense
of cultural identity. I am a practicing Reform Jew. To me, being Jewish
involves participation in Jewish worship, knowledge of Jewish history and
tradition, affiliation with Jewish institutions, particularly a synagogue, and
a poorly rationalized, ad hoc relationship with Jewish law. Cultural Jews would
describe what it means to them to be Jewish very differently. I worry that the
conception of Jewish culture on which they stand cannot justify bearing the
costs of being perpetual Jewish strangers wherever they live.
It is precisely because of these
shared sensibilities that I found Kwall’s book to be so frustrating. I wanted
her book to discuss this third issue in much more depth than it does.
Professor Kwall’s message to
cultural Jews is that if they care about maintaining the particularity of Jewish
identity and tradition, they have to connect more closely than they do to
Jewish law. Jewish culture divorced from Jewish law cannot persevere. Indeed,
it makes little sense to act as if Jewish culture can exist in any meaningful
sense that is separate from its Jewish law roots.
Why should cultural Jews be
persuaded by this argument? One answer is grounded in the principles of
cultural analysis. Law and culture are integrated. Neither can really be
understood in isolation from the other. This
abstract conclusion, however, doesn’t persuasively explain why it is impossible
to have an enduring Jewish identity unsupported by religious law. Why is law an essential condition for cultural
continuity?
Part of the problem here relates to what exactly Professor
Kwall means by Jewish law. Sometimes she describes Jewish law so expansively it
seems to encompass the entire megillah
of Jewish tradition, customs, and history. In this broad sense, Jewish culture
is unavoidably intertwined with Jewish law. This seems almost self-evident and
I doubt many cultural Jews would dispute this contention. But I also doubt they
would think her argument is inconsistent with their understanding of their
Jewish identity. They acknowledge connecting with some Jewish customs and
traditions as distinctive aspects of Jewish culture. What they reject is the
idea that these customs and traditions must be obeyed because they are divine
commandments. If by cultural Jews, we mean secular Jews, and that is how the
term is typically used, the problem is not only that they doubt that these
commandments are an accurate description of G-d’s laws. Cultural, as opposed to
religious, Jews, do not believe in G-d.
Defining Jewish law more narrowly
does not mitigate this problem. Kwall explains that historically, Jewish law as
law is what distinguished Jews from non-Jews. Many Jewish customs, traditions,
and ethical values may not constitute divine obligations. However, their
ultimate source is Jewish law, the halakhah.
Thus, Jewish law is part of the DNA of the cultural Jew, whether they know
it or not. But how does this attenuated
historical analysis demonstrate that culture alone cannot support Jewish
identity. A tradition may have independent value or provide a feeling of
distinctive communal membership regardless of its source. To the cultural Jew,
a tradition’s virtues over time are irrelevant to its origin in Jewish law. Many
atheists may concede that religion was the source of ethical principles they
endorse today from a humanist perspective. That recognition does not persuade
them to connect with the religious roots of their ethics.
Professor Kwall says very little in
her book about G-d. I found this surprising.
I think the primary reason that cultural Jews see no reason to obey Jewish law
or even to respond to its requirements is that they deny its legitimacy. If G-d
does not exist, what justifies conferring law making authority on religious
leaders or compels adherence to religious law? Exactly how are cultural Jews to
authentically connect with Jewish law, as Kwall urges them to do, when they
reject an essential premise on which the law is based?
Professor Kwall's impressive demonstration that there is a
human element to Jewish law does not resolve this problem. Law is obligatory.
There has to be a reason for people to obey what purports to be law. Jews who
believe that Jewish law reflects the best attempts of mortals to understand and
communicate G-d's commands have a sufficient reason to obey such laws -- even
if the laws do not represent the literal expression of G-d's will and,
accordingly, may be mistaken in their requirements. Without this
acknowledgement of Devine inspiration, however, it is difficult to understand
what gives Jewish law obligatory power. Jewish law was not followed because of
its functional utility or a democratic consensus endorsing it as the will of
the people. It commanded allegiance either as G-d's will or as human mediation of
G-d's will. If cultural Jews do not believe that Jewish law reflects the Devine
in any meaningful way, it is hard to understand how they can expected to adhere
to such laws or to justify their conduct by reference to them.
Even for religious Jews, there remains
the question of whether Jewish identity can be grounded on ethics and worship
without an accompanying commitment to obeying traditional Jewish law. Some Jews
today engage in traditional worship services (or more unconventional modes of
worship) for relational rather than legal reasons. They value Jewish moral
conscience rather than legal obligations. These are not cultural Jews. Yet they
can be asked a question roughly similar to the admonition Professor Kwall
directed at cultural Jews. Can Jewish worship and ethics can be separated from
Jewish law, and, if that is possible, will it provide a strong enough
foundation for the continuation of a distinctive Jewish identity? And if it will not, can the requirements of
Jewish continuity instill a renewed connection to laws that no longer resonate
in the minds and hearts of many Jews.
Alan
Brownstein is Professor of Law, Boochever and Bird Chair for the Study and Teaching of Freedom and Equality. You can reach him by e-mail at aebrownstein at ucdavis.edu