E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Along with others I believe the new immigration initiative is a
constitutional exercise of DHS’s broad discretion over enforcement of the
immigration statutes. The Office of
Legal Counsel opinion provides an impressive and careful assessment of the
initiative’s legality. OLC deserves credit
both for making the opinion publicly available and undertaking to identify the
metes and bounds of constitutional exercises of enforcement discretion.
OLC identifies four principles as delimiting the permissible
scope of enforcement discretion, two of which strike me as meriting special
emphasis. The first is the requirement
that enforcement decisions must comport with statutory policies and cannot
represent a surreptitious attempt by the executive branch to rewrite the
statutes at issue. The second—the
constitutional bona fides of which I question—is that “a general policy of
non-enforcement that forecloses case-by-case discretion poses special risks
that the agency has exceeded the bounds of its enforcement discretion.” (OLC Op. at 7).
A requirement that enforcement decisions must constitute
good faith efforts to implement governing statutes (assuming those statutes are
constitutional) strikes me as a no brainer.
This is the minimum constitutional demand imposed by the Take Care
Clause’s requirement of faithful execution of the laws. Whether such good faith efforts preclude
invocation of presidential priorities when these priorities are compatible with
underlying statutes is a harder question, as Adam Cox and Cristina Rodriguez suggest. More
generally, the principle that enforcement discretion must comport with
statutory policy is not what’s in dispute.
Instead, it’s OLC’s application of this requirement — on the one hand,
to uphold DHS’s proposal to grant deferred action status to parents of U.S.
citizens or legal permanent residents, despite estimates that this may shield
up to four million immigrants from deportation; and on the other, to conclude
that it would be impermissible to grant deferred action status to parents of beneficiaries
of the 2012 DACA program.
Still, the initiative’s statutory underpinnings are a
critical feature of OLC’s analysis, and to my mind an important and appropriate
one. As Marty Lederman notes, rather than asserting inherent presidential power, OLC’s
assessed DHS’s proposed actions entirely through the prism of delegated
statutory authority. That statutory
focus will be a central factor in determining the opinion’s impact in future
contexts.
OLC’s suggestion that exercises of enforcement discretion
must preserve an opportunity for case-by-case determinations is much harder to
justify. OLC invokes lower court
decisions in support of such a case-by-case requirement, but these decisions
address a different issue, namely whether an agency’s adoption of a general enforcement
policy should be deemed discretionary action that is presumptively exempt from
judicial review under the Administrative Procedure Act. The two questions are significantly distinct; it’s
well-established that an agency decision can be judicially reviewable yet
nonetheless constitute a legitimate exercise of discretion. Moreover, at most these decisions identify
case-by-case determinations as enforcement discretion’s paradigmatic form. But that is a far cry from concluding that a
purely general policy alone cannot qualify.
OLC also suggests that a case-by-case outlet is important to
guard against the executive branch trumping statutory policy, however the basis
for this connection isn’t obvious to me.
Nothing in the categorical nature of an enforcement policy entails that
it will be more likely used to defeat statutory policies rather than enforce
them. Insofar as categorical policies
make enforcement choices more transparent and better constrain low-level
discretion, they actually represent an important mechanism for enforcing adherence to governing law. To be sure, the Supreme Court has indicated
that exercises of discretion in the immigration context may statutorily require
“some level of individualized determination.”
(Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292,
313 (1993)). That would support OLC’s
emphasis on opportunities for individualized determinations under the
initiative, but doesn’t justify a broader principle that all constitutional
exercises of prosecutorial discretion must have a case-by-case element.
Most importantly, an insistence on preserving case-by-case assessment
ignores the constitutional values served by categorical enforcement policies. Meaningful supervision over case-by-case removal
decisions is hard. Precluding
prospective and categorical articulation of immigration enforcement priorities
is thus tantamount to insisting that nonenforcement decisions must be made by
lower-level officials. Such a requirement
stands fundamentally at odds with our constitutional structure, which I have argued embodies a duty to supervise exercises of delegated
power. On this view, by openly stating a
generally applicable policy and instituting an administrative scheme and
guidance to implement that policy, President Obama and Secretary Johnson were
fulfilling their constitutional duty. This
positive constitutional case for categorical enforcement oversight deserves
greater weight in assessing the initiative’s constitutionality.
Gillian Metzger is Stanley H. Fuld Professor of Law at Columbia Law School. You can reach her by e-mail at gillian.metzger at law.columbia.edu