E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Thanks
so much to Linda McClain for organizing this symposium and Jack Balkin for
hosting it. I am delighted to engage in a week-long conversation about family
law, which is, as I argue in my book, an under-appreciated factor contributing
to inequality in the United States.
Elizabeth
Scott has provided a terrific start to the symposium, raising a host of
important issues. Scott has already given a brief overview of the central
argument of the book—that families are essential to human flourishing but that
too often family law undermines family relationships—so I will jump right into
her arguments. Scott contends that although the U.S. should adopt my proposals,
it is unlikely that the country will do so, at least to the extent I recommend.
Scott identifies both political and pragmatic reasons for resistance. She notes
the unwillingness to re-think the current distribution of wealth as well as a preference
for programs that focus on tangible harms and produce positive outcomes in the
near-term rather than programs that focus on diffuse harms and have either a
remote or unclear payoff. She thus distinguishes teen pregnancy prevention
programs (more likely to win support) from efforts to encourage co-parenting by
low-income, unmarried fathers (more likely to face opposition). I agree with this
view as a predictive matter, but much of what I call for in the book, even those
programs that might seem to address diffuse harms with remote payoffs, can be
re-framed in the way Scott suggests.
Consider
my focus on childhood development from birth to age three. As overwhelming
research has established—from the Adverse Childhood Experiences Study to
the research on
brain development—this period is absolutely critical to healthy child
development. When things go wrong during early childhood, the effects can be
felt for a lifetime. Importantly, much of the potential harm stems from problems
in the parent-child relationship. Of the ten ACE factors, for
example, nine pertain solely to family relationships. Consistent with Scott’s insight,
then, it is possible to characterize the harm from family dysfunction and
efforts to remedy that harm as both concrete and immediate.
My
proffered solution of improving family functioning could be understood as an
effort with a remote or uncertain payoff, but here, again, it is possible to
frame the intervention in the terms Scott proposes. Part of the answer is
framing the intervention as an indispensable part of the solution. Some
scholars prefer programs that provide benefits directly to children. Economist
Janet Currie, for example, argues that it is more effective social welfare
policy to supply children with in-kind benefits, such as food, medical care,
and housing, than to pursue programs that try to change parental behavior and
thus influence children indirectly. (The Invisible Safety Net, p. 8, although I note that she was talking about the uncertain benefits of cash
welfare programs that encourage parents to work and not other parenting
programs more broadly). In-kind benefits are vital, but they address only part
of the problem. It is essential to improve the quality of the parent-child
relationship as well, even if the benefit cannot be measured in calories
provided, vaccinations administered, and housing units newly available. This
orientation thus requires a more nuanced understanding of the role of
relationships in child development and the irreplaceable role played by
families. Nuance may not be a strong suit in American politics, but the benefit
from strong families is anything but uncertain.
It
is also important to remember, as Scott notes, that many efforts at immediate
help—which can come across as appeals to increase the social safety net—can
face political headwinds as well. By contrast, attempts to improve family
functioning may appeal across partisan lines in ways that such increased
support likely would not. Tax and transfer programs are an essential component
of the safety net, but the American public is not going to invest substantially
more money in these programs anytime soon. I agree with Scott that universal
programs are more likely to win widespread support, but Scott acknowledges that
it is difficult to find the funding for such programs in the current economic
climate. A focus on family functioning presents an opportunity to “talk
purple,” across “red” and “blue” political lines, as I suggest in the last
chapter of my book. There may be a fortuitous alignment between advocates on
the left, who see the connection between families and inequality, and advocates
on the right, who want to address family breakdown.
Of
course there is risk in this, too. In the family law context, explicit
efforts to change the behavior of family members are often intrusive,
judgmental programs that denigrate and marginalize low-income families and
especially families of color. From sterilization efforts that continued well
into the twentieth century to the modern day child welfare system, when the
state seeks to change behaviors in families, too often this means pathologizing
the family behavior of some families. This is a constant concern and we must
remain vigilant about it, while also recognizing the need for additional state
support. But with that caveat clearly in mind, I remain hopeful that
strengthening families can appeal broadly.
In sum, Scott’s insights offer a roadmap for re-framing the
kinds of programs that address family functioning. I am more than open to this
re-framing because what I really care about is the substance—improving family
relationships so that children can flourish.
Clare
Huntington, Professor of Law, Fordham Law School. Professor Huntington may be reached at chuntingtonatlaw.fordham.edu