E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
In his post summarizing his recent law review article, Dale
Carpenter draws from the Court’s discriminatory purpose jurisprudence, most
notably its 1977 Arlington Heights
case, to find guideposts for identifying animus. Thus, according to Dale, Arlington Heights factors such as the substantive or procedural
deviations reflected in the challenged law, and (more distantly in his
analysis) the degree of the law’s disparate impact, all feed into the
determination whether a challenged law reflects animus. That conclusion then triggers (in his fifth
step) a flipping of the burden of proof onto the government – and hence, a
decision by the court to go beyond traditional rational basis review, with all
its government-friendly presumptions.
I don’t necessarily disagree with Dale’s analogizing to Arlington Heights, although I don’t
believe every Arlington Heights
factor can be found in each and every of the canonical animus cases. (I think Dale agrees with that last
statement.) But I would caution about
taking that analogy to the next level.
If we follow the Arlington Heights
path, then a facially race-neutral/facially non-animus-based law, if unmasked
to be really race-based/animus-based, triggers heightened judicial
scrutiny. In other words, in the race
context, if a court concludes, based on Arlington
Heights, that a law is race-based, that’s not the end of the case: instead,
the Court then applies the strict scrutiny that it has continually cautioned is
“not necessarily fatal in fact.”
By contrast, when Dale lumps into the animus identification
phase of the analysis the burden-shifting that he identifies as his fifth step,
he seems to be suggesting that the result of those five steps should be (or
maybe just is, as a descriptive matter) the end of the case. I think that’s the correct approach. As I suggested in my response to Susannah’s
initial post, it seems to me that a conclusion of animus should end the case,
in the plaintiff’s favor. I’m concerned that
uncritical application of the Arlington
Heights analogy would lead courts to conclude that an animus finding simply
triggers more searching review. To be
sure, Justice O’Connor’s equal protection concurrence in Lawrence at least implies this latter approach. (In Lawrence
she wrote: “When a law exhibits . . . a desire to harm a politically
unpopular group, we have applied a more searching form of rational basis review
to strike down such laws under the Equal Protection Clause.”) But that approach opens up the (perhaps just
theoretical) possibility that a law reflecting animus could in fact be upheld,
if it satisfies such heightened review.
Dale’s approach is different, as it “bakes in” to the animus determination
itself the heightened ends-means review that Justice O’Connor implies is a
distinct phase of the analysis.
This may be splitting hairs.
But I think analytical clarity is furthered by splitting these
particular locks. “Bad intent” is a
concept thrown around a lot in equal protection doctrine. Justice O’Connor herself tossed it back and
forth in her Croson opinion when she
expressed concern that race classifications of any sort carried a high risk of
the “bad intent” of “simple racial politics.”
Note that this latter version of “bad intent” was not the sort addressed
by Arlington Heights or Washington v. Davis: the Richmond
contracting set-aside was explicitly race-based, thus, there was no need to
determine if the government “intended” to classify based on race. Rather, the type of bad intent she addressed
in Croson was of the “ultimate” sort
– was the city’s MBE plan an unconstitutional use of race? – rather than of the
“threshold” sort – was the plan race-based, such that it triggered strict
scrutiny, which might or might not be fatal in this particular case?
To me, a finding of animus ought to be akin to
what I call here an “ultimate” finding of unconstitutionality. That approach makes animus fit more
comfortably with the earlier idea of class legislation, that my own post
identified as a precursor the modern concept of animus. Dale’s analysis, by baking into that finding
the heightened ends-means review we see in lots of animus cases to date (e.g., Cleburne and Romer),
appears consistent with that view. But
we need to be careful about analogies. Bill Araiza is a Professor at Brooklyn Law School. He can be reached at: bill.araiza at brooklaw.edu. Posted
11:07 AM
by Guest Blogger [link]