E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
Here’s
a familiar rule of First Amendment law:free speech protection does not apply, or applies only weakly, to what
are often referred to as “low-value” categories of speech. As recently as 2010, the Supreme Court declared in United States v. Stevens that First
Amendment protections extend equally to all speech and expression except those “well defined and narrowly limited
classes” of low-value speech, “the prevention and punishment of which have
never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem.”
In an important
new paper, Genevieve Lakier shows that this story is false. In early American courts, all speech—even low-value
speech—was protected against prior restraint, and almost all speech— even
high-value speech—was subject to criminal punishment when it appeared to pose a
threat to the public order of society, broadly defined. It was only after the
New Deal Court embraced the modern, libertarian conception of freedom of speech
that courts began to treat high and low-value speech qualitatively differently.
The fake
historical narrative was offhandedly invented by Justice Frank Murphy in
Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire (1942).The
passage the Stevens Court quoted declares:
“There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited
classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which has never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and
obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or ‘‘fighting’’
words—those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an
immediate breach of the peace. It has been well observed that such utterances
are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social
value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is
clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and morality.”
The
passage closely tracks the following, from Zechariah Chafee’s important book,
Free Speech in the United States (1942), which Lakier quotes:
“obscenity, profanity, and
gross libels upon individuals . . . are too well-recognized to question their constitutionality,
but I believe that if properly limited they fall outside the protection of the
free speech clauses as I have defined them. My reason is not that they existed
at common law before the constitutions, for a similar argument would apply to the
crime of sedition, which was abolished by the First Amendment. . . . The true
explanation is that profanity and indecent talk and pictures, which do not form
an essential part of any exposition of ideas, have a very slight social value
as a step toward truth, which is clearly outweighed by the social interests in
order, morality, the training of the young, and the peace of mind of those who
hear and see.”
Lakier
writes:
“Justice Murphy borrowed a
great deal from this passage in constructing his opinion in Chaplinsky, as is evident from the
opinion’s text. Nevertheless, there is a crucial difference between Chafee’s
argument and Murphy’s recapitulation of the argument in Chaplinsky—namely, that Chafee never claimed the distinction he
drew between what he called the “normal” criminal laws of obscenity, profanity,
and libel and the abnormal and unconstitutional sedition statutes was based on
historical practice.”
Her discovery of the Chafee
passage is only one of the virtues of this terrific paper.She also displays an impressive command of
nineteenth century free speech law.
The Court today declares, as a
basis for rejecting state attempts to prohibit such novelties as videos of
animals being tortured, that the only permissible content-based regulations of speech are those
that target speech that was historically unprotected. If that were true, then
child pornography – a category unknown to the law until the late twentieth
century – would likewise be protected.
Murphy
was merely making an offhand claim to shore up the value judgment that underlay
his holding.The modern Court, in yet another
exercise in phony originalism, elevates that claim to official doctrine,
and purports to be relying on an ancient understanding when in fact it is doing
nothing of the kind.The value judgments
in the present doctrine may or may not be defensible, but they need to be
defended as such, not cloaked behind bad history.
Lakier’s
piece should definitively put this dishonest bit of doctrine to rest.