E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
The basic elements of contemporary Religion Clauses doctrine have hidden in
plain sight. American law treats religion as a distinctive human good but
protects it from political manipulation by denying the state the power to take
sides on any theological question. This approach entails rules of
disestablishment, such as the secular purpose requirement, which prevent the
government from using coercive laws to proclaim religious truth. It also
entails that it is permissible for the legislature to recognize religion’s
value by accommodating it. American law insists (with an important exception)
on neutrality among religions. Its understanding of “religion” is calculatedly
vague, allowing it to accommodate claims of conscience that sufficiently
resemble religious claims. Because scholars regard existing law with contempt,
they have spent most of their efforts engaging with each other. An alternate
universe of theoretical possibilities has developed, a battleground of
competing visions of the Religion Clauses. In this world, American law
sometimes goes unnoticed altogether.
Micah Schwartzman is one of our finest young scholars of law and religion
and has brought sophisticated philosophical analysis to some perennial
problems. His analytical skills are conspicuously on display in What If Religion is Not Special?, recently published in the
University of Chicago Law Review. He carefully anatomizes a
number of competing positions in the law review literature and shows the weaknesses
of each, leaving himself with, as he puts it, an “intellectual ache”: it
appears to him that the commitments of our constitutional regime cannot be
justified. His article is a valuable contribution. But it can mislead the
reader because, as in so much literature in this field, the actual law of the
United States escapes his vision.
I elaborate this critique in a new article in the online edition of the Law
Review, available here.