E-mail:
Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com
Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu
Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu
Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu
Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu
Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com
Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu
Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu
Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu
Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu
Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu
Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu
Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu
Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu
Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu
David Luban david.luban at gmail.com
Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu
Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu
Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu
John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu
Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com
Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com
Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com
Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu
Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu
David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu
Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu
K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu
Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu
Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu
David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu
Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu
Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu
Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu
Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu
We are grateful to Eric
Blumenson for his sympathetic yet critical review of our book, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities,
and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013). If Sotirios Barber is
concerned that our civic liberalism may be too thin (as compared with a
comprehensive liberal perfectionism), Blumenson
worries that it may be too thick (as compared with liberal neutrality).
Blumenson begins with a gracious
and graceful summary of our view, bringing out the “liberal virtues” in Ordered Liberty. He praises our
project’s attempt to find common ground with Michael Sandel’s civic
republicanism and Mary Ann Glendon’s communitarianism through a “positive
theory of ordered liberty that both protects individual choices and promotes
certain virtues.” Yet, he has two main criticisms of our theory. One, he
contends that “remain[ing] neutral” between controversial comprehensive
conceptions of the good life and promoting moral goods “that are common to
diverse comprehensive systems” is “more easily said than done.” Two, he raises
doubts about whether the lines that we draw between our civic liberalism and a
comprehensive liberal perfectionism can hold in hard cases, such as not
recognizing polygamous marriage and banning the headscarf.
We shall respond to each of
these criticisms. First, we fear that Blumenson has misinterpreted our project
as aiming merely to provide an “exception” or large “footnote” to liberal
neutrality. We mean instead to develop a civic liberalism that is an
alternative to liberal neutrality and to comprehensive liberal perfectionism.
Our theory (a) permits governmental encouragement (though not compulsion) of
responsible exercise of rights; (b) justifies a “formative project” of
government inculcating civic virtues (though not moral virtues simpliciter) upon which ordered liberty
depends; ( c) justifies rights on the grounds both of individual autonomy and
of the moral goods furthered by protecting them; (d) adjusts basic liberties
where they conflict in order to secure equal citizenship for all; and (e)
protects basic liberties stringently though not absolutely through reasoned
judgment rather than falling for the “myth of strict scrutiny for fundamental
rights” under the Due Process Clause (pp. 237-72). Our view is thus
considerably different from liberal neutrality as commonly understood.
Second, Blumenson acknowledges
that we attempt to draw such lines between our civic liberalism and
comprehensive liberal perfectionism. But he worries that our line-drawing
“fails in the[] harder cases” like polygamy and the headscarf and fails to
provide “enough guidance to identifying ‘unreasonable ways of life.’”
We have two responses to these
worries. One, it is important not to expect too much from a general political
or constitutional theory. Here we take inspiration and instruction from John
Rawls, who, through his celebrated humility, imparted wisdom in judging what we
can expect from a theory. It may be too much to expect that a theory squarely
resolve all the hardest cases. It may be enough that it articulates a guiding
framework through which we can think more clearly and reasonably about the
issues. We do not presume to have resolved all of the hard cases that arise in
a diverse liberal democracy such as our own. But we do claim to have put
forward a guiding framework for securing ordered liberty and for making
reasoned judgments that will enable us better to address these cases.
Two, we are not clear why
Blumenson thinks that the lines we draw fail with respect to polygamy and the
headscarf. We did not address these two controversies in our book, but here’s a
sketch of an approach that it would support. The right to same-sex marriage, we
argue there, is justifiable on grounds both of individual autonomy and of moral
goods fostered through protecting it. It is also justifiable on the ground that
recognizing it is necessary to secure the status of equal citizenship for gays
and lesbians. We would argue that these justifications suggest distinctions
between same-sex marriage and polygamy. We also would argue, to invoke
limitations drawn in Lawrence v. Texas
(2003), that concern for consent and coercion, as well as abuse or harm of
minors, distinguishes polygamy. So, too, does concern over sex equality. Of
course, contemporary practitioners of polygamy suing to challenge the
criminalization of polygamy (e.g., the Brown family from Sister Wives) counter with that same language from Lawrence, arguing that consensual
polygamy involving adults involves none of those harms and that banning it
violates their constitutional right to be let alone and their right to free
exercise of religion. These two contrasting views of polygamy raise empirical
questions. Women involved in fundamentalist polygamous communities differ in
their assessments of it. Without embracing the equation made in Reynolds v. United States (1878) of
polygamy with “the patriarchal principle” and “stationary despotism,” we find
it persuasive that, based on “the most comprehensive judicial record” on
polygamy “ever produced,” the Supreme Court of British Columbia ruled in 2011
that polygamy was “essentially about harm,” rather than freedom of association and
religion, and that Canada’s criminal ban could survive a challenge under the
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms because of Parliament’s “reasoned
apprehension of harm arising out of the practice of polygamy...to women, to
children, to society, and to the institution of monogamous marriage.” We can
say or accept all this while remaining within civic liberalism and without
obliterating the lines between it and comprehensive liberal perfectionism.
The headscarf controversy or,
more recently, France’s ban on wearing the full veil in public, raises
challenging issues about the best way for a government to promote core
principles of (in France) liberty, equality, and fraternity, particularly
equality, while also respecting the autonomy and religious freedom of women. We
do not have the expertise or the space here to speak definitively about how to
resolve that controversy. On the one hand, a Parliamentary Commission’s study
concluded that the full veil was “an intolerable infringement on the freedom and
the dignity of women.” In particular, witnesses and experts stressed the
importance of the face in social and public life. There was also testimony that
some women wore the veil due to coercion. On the other hand, some human rights
organizations argue that such bans interfere with women’s fundamental human
rights in the name of misguided protectionism. Insightful critics of such bans
also warn that the veil too often serves a symbol of terrorism and militant
Islam that seemingly threatens Western nations. Further, how will excluding
veiled women from the public sphere help them in any way? Martha Nussbaum has
made powerful arguments that France’s ban reflects a “new religious
intolerance.”
Blumenson may think that
polygamy and the headscarf (or veil) are especially hard cases for us because
he thinks that the only lines we draw concern (1) the civic virtues of the good
citizen versus (2) the moral virtues or excellence of the good person. But our
civic liberalism is concerned not only to inculcate civic virtues but also to
develop the capacities for democratic and personal self-government and to
secure the status of equal citizenship for all. It is also concerned to frame
and adjust clashes of rights between liberty and equal citizenship. As we have
tried to indicate, public values like concern for these capacities, for
children as future citizens, for the status of equal citizenship, and for harm,
together with the need to adjust such clashes, come centrally into play with
respect to both polygamy and the headscarf (or veil). Our civic liberalism,
with its concern to secure ordered liberty, provides a framework for addressing
such issues.