Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Racist Progressives, Meet Hard-Hearted Libertarians
|
Friday, October 15, 2010
Racist Progressives, Meet Hard-Hearted Libertarians
Brian Tamanaha
With the resurgence of the use of the term “progressive” by liberals, libertarians have taken to reminding liberals that their turn-of-the-century progressive forebears were virulent racists. According to libertarians, when the social reformist impulse of progressivism mixed with the personal racism of progressives, a toxic brew resulted that led to the legal oppression of blacks and other racial minorities. “The ideas of race and color were powerful, controlling elements in progressive social and political thinking,” [David Southern] argues. “And this fixation on race explains how democratic reform and racism went hand-in-hand.” Libertarians even blame progressives for Jim Crow laws.
Comments:
Libertarians should be far more embarrassed by the way self-described libertarians reacted to the Civil Rights Movement; indeed, they should be embarrassed by the way some react today to the idea of equal rights. Like the Right generally, they just can't seem to get over race.
The sins of the progressives, whatever they were, are long in the past. The sins of libertarians plague us today.
I'm sorry, but your argument strikes me as not at all fair.
First, you start by comparing the racism of early progressives with the social darwinism of early libertarians. But then you conclude by contrasting the removal of racism from progressivism with libertarianism's retention of "the doctrine that government activities should be strictly limited to protecting property, enforcing contracts, and maintaining order." Your argument gets its rhetorical force from an equivocation between limited government and social darwinism. Although you quietly slide from one to the other, social darwinism and limited government are emphatically not the same thing (as you implicitly acknowledge when you note that Mises was not a social darwinist). There is nothing inconsistent or unlibertarian about believing in strictly limited government while simultaneously advocating private charity and other noncoercive means of helping the less fortunate. And indeed there are strains of libertarian thought going back well over a century that have advocated precisely that. Second, you say that "the doctrine that government activities should be strictly limited to protecting property, enforcing contracts, and maintaining order is built into libertarianism." Like any political movement, libertarianism has many different strains, both historically and today, and your description certainly fits one major strain. But any description purporting to identify core ideas that are "built into" libertarianism that excludes major figures like F.A. Hayek and Milton Friedman from the libertarian tent (both were proponents of a substantial public safety net) is simply not serious. There are major libertarian organizations today that are clearly far more strongly influenced by the thought of Hayek and Friedman than by Mises (Cato, for example). Finally, how would you feel about this argument if it were turned around: While social darwinism can be severed without loss from libertarianism (and indeed has been), the doctrine that an individual's rights and interests should be defined solely by their membership in a particular class or social group is built into progressivism. I think that's analogous to your treatment of libertarianism, and equally unfair.
Michael,
I agree that social Darwinism is not inherent to libertarianism--indeed I thought I said that (I should have been more explicit). The point of my comparison is that racism is not an inherent component of progressivism, but limited government is inherent to libertarianism. Hence, progressivism can drop racism but liberalism cannot drop the notion of the extremely minimalist state. You are correct that there are strains of liberalism that depart from von Mises, but as you note the strain I mention is a major one. Friedman's ideas are certainly in tune with von Mises' views. (Hayek was less extreme than either, and supported social insurance plans.) Mark, Much of the opposition to the civil rights movement was driven by racism. I would not say, however, that the opposition of some prominent libertarians to the civil rights movement was the product of racism. Libertarians can produce principled reasons for their opposition to civil rights legislation. Brian
Much? Most, I would say.
It's always hard to judge what's in someone's mind, but the way I look at it is this: libertarian arguments gave (and continue to give) aid and comfort to the racists, and libertarians never seem to care much; indeed, they continue to work on the same side of the political spectrum, supporting many of the same candidates and most of the same policies. If libertarians aren't themselves afflicted with the disease of racism, they are the Typhoid Marys of it.
Prof. Tamanaha,
It's true that you never explicitly said that social Darwinism is inherent to libertarianism, but I think it's pretty easy to read your argument that way. You say: [L]ibertarians can protest that heartless social Darwinism is not inherent to libertarianism. We could call a truce and stop trying to smear contemporary versions of these ideas with the ignorance and sins of their forebears. That would be nice and neighborly, but it’s not quite right. You then explain that while progressivism has abandoned racism, strictly limited government is "built into" libertarianism. That sounds to me like you're implicitly equating limited government with social darwinism. The only clue suggesting otherwise is the parenthetical noting that Mises was not a social darwinist. Maybe I'm being overly sensitive, but it definitely reads to me like an attempt to tar modern day libertarians with the social darwinist label. I also question this: Friedman's ideas are certainly in tune with von Mises' views. The impression you give of Mises (I've read very little of his work, so I'm relying on your characterization) is that he was wholly opposed to government provision of basic social services. Friedman on the other hand is famous as the inventer of the Earned Income Tax Credit. The New York Times called him "the architect of the most successful social welfare program of all time." In education, Friedman is considered by many to be the father of the school voucher movement -- an attempt to change the method of allocating government education funds. In any case, I appreciate you taking the time to respond to my earlier comment.
"The point of my comparison is that racism is not an inherent component of progressivism, but limited government is inherent to libertarianism. Hence, progressivism can drop racism but liberalism cannot drop the notion of the extremely minimalist state."
True, Brian, but your argument that, to paraphrase, "(extreme) libertarians are more saddled with the legacy of racism," loses pretty much all of its force if a minimalist state can be proven superior without resort to social darwinism...which of course is what minarchists contend. (FWIW, I consider myself an ex-minarchist and a presently moderate libertarian.) Your more modest argument for equivalence is better founded.
A short addendum: The minimum wage is an example of a policy that progressives once supported for racist/sexist reasons, i.e. to exclude women and people of color from labor markets (see, e.g., the work of David Bernstein) but now support it in the good faith belief that the minimum wage is good for workers generally.
Opponents of the minimum wage like myself can make a pretty reasonable argument that that factual claim is wrong -- that, in fact, the original progressives were actually choosing an effective means to achieve their ends. But I'm not comfortable with arguments that the case for the minimum wage and modern progressives are "tainted." I think libertarians are entitled to the same respect.
It's always hard to judge what's in someone's mind, but the way I look at it is this: libertarian arguments gave (and continue to give) aid and comfort to the racists, and libertarians never seem to care much; indeed, they continue to work on the same side of the political spectrum, supporting many of the same candidates and most of the same policies.
If libertarians aren't themselves afflicted with the disease of racism, they are the Typhoid Marys of it. This isn't quite right. They do continue to work on that side of the political spectrum, but many (not all, but many) have made their peace with civil rights laws as well. But it isn't quite wrong either. I have noticed when having discussions with libertarians how, for lack of a better term, clueless they are about issues of race. They simply don't understand why a free market would permit irrational discrimination, and figure there must be some inherently "statist" reason behind any form of unfair conduct. And further, they don't seem to understand how people can suffer injuries from discrimination. Yes, of course they get it when it involves fire hoses in the south in the 1960's, but they will argue that blacks could just form their own businesses, or sexual harassment victims could just get over themselves or quit their jobs, or gays can just stay in the closet or make contracts with their loved ones. The lived experience of discrimination seems to sail directly over their heads. And I suspect that is almost inevitable when you have a predominantly (not exclusively, but predominantly) white male social movement that preaches an "I've got mine" ethos.
Matthew,
There are aspects of libertarian thought that I am drawn to, and I admire Hayek (who I have written about). Indeed I consider myself a social libertarian--yes, I get the contradiction--along the lines of L.T. Hobhouse. My post does not "disrespect" libertarianism simply by pointing out that a minimalist view of government entails tough consequences for real people on the bottom. Both Hayek and von Mises forthrightly acknowledged this as the unfortunate price that must be paid for a bigger economic pie--and they argued that despite times of immediate suffering the poor would be better off in the long run. The point of my post is to suggest that libertarians are equally vulnerable to attacks on intellectual ancestors. There seems to have been a lot of "leading progressives were racists" talk coming from libertarian circles lately. That's fun stuff, of course, and I showed that progressives can play it too. Of course it is more important to talk about what these respective views hold today. Hence my closing line about continuing echoes in contemporary libertarian thought. Brian
Prof. Tamanaha:
But classical liberals have their own embarrassing grandparents. Herbert Spencer, the most influential advocate of laissez faire in nineteenth century America, opposed all government aid to the poor and infirm because it thwarted the biological law that the weakest should die. How does "the most influential advocate of laissez faire" become a progressive or liberal? Cheers,
many (not all, but many) have made their peace with civil rights laws as well.
Some have, to be sure. But I generally find them grudging in their acceptance, utterly unwilling to extend them, and all too ready to accept an excuse to limit them.
Arne,
The term "classical liberal" does not mean "liberal" in the contemporary sense of liberal politics. This flip in meaning is a major source of confusion. Classical liberals are the forebears of contemporary libertarianism, which today is seen as a strain of conservative thought (although the classical liberals were NOT conservatives, and they make an odd match with social conservatives). Their main focus is on maximal individual liberty, with minimum interference from government. Brian
American populism as "progressive" was a definition that only had currency in a very narrow period centering around TR's career. Well that is my perception. These terms are slippery as the definitions often evolve as movements define themselves and are defined by their opponents.
TR, so oddly in many ways a Republican, had to banish the socialist roots of some of his policies so he and his supporters called them Progressive. In coming days you will hear about the certain legislative move to fix the risk of MBS holder putbacks to the originators. Retroactively altering contracts which stipulated how property titles and credit notes based upon 200 years of American law and practice as it evolved. This will be defined as Conservative and it's opponents will be Liberals and Progressives. Times change and so does the meaning of words.
Let me see if I have this right. Back in the 50s those in the South who were for civil rights called ourselves "liberals", those against we called "conservatives". Now, because "liberal" has been corrupted to the point of being an epithet, some "liberals" (but not "classical liberals" - those are "libertarians", more or less) have adopted "progressive" as a label. But "progressivism" has an unfortunate history that means those who supported civil rights when it wasn't popular to do so can now be accused of racism by "conservatives" - who once were, at least in the South, unequivocally the "racists". And because "libertarians" can be accused of being "Social Darwinists" due to being for minimalist government, they in effect are also "racists" since the consequences would fall hardest on minorities. From which I conclude that we have finally found common ground for all the major political currents - racism!
Is there any possibility that those who would like to engage in meaningful discourse might be better off just discussing individual issues without trying to fit themselves and others into apparently extremely porous ideological boxes?
"Back in the 50s those in the South who were for civil rights called ourselves "liberals","
Try to add the modifier "some of" to your vocabulary. Being for civil rights was hardly an exclusive pastime of people who called themselves "liberals".
indeed, they should be embarrassed by the way some react today to the idea of equal rights. Like the Right generally, they just can't seem to get over race.
Uh, it's the left that opposes color-blind policies in the U.S. today, not the right. It's the left that supports departments in academia whose sole purpose is to fan racial grievances. Identity politics is a creature of the mainstream left. Racial bloc voting is a left phenomenon in the U.S. The right is long past race. It's the left that can't get over it. libertarian arguments gave (and continue to give) aid and comfort to the racists, What racists? There is no constituency for racism in the U.S. anymore. Some have [made their peace with civil rights laws], to be sure. But I generally find them grudging in their acceptance, utterly unwilling to extend them, and all too ready to accept an excuse to limit them. When we discuss the original enactment of the civil rights laws, you explain that they were justified because the market never could have solved the problem because of the horrible conditions in the Jim Crow south. And yet, now that conditions are no longer anything like that, instead of conceding that they're no longer needed, you want to "extend" them. Which tends to call into question the sincerity of the original argument.
Libertarians would use the power of the state to oppress minorities. For example, by expecting police to arrest minorities for "trespassing" onto property that a racist white owns and holds out for public use - except for minorities. Segregation whether it be de facto or de jure relies on the power of the state in one way or another.
Hm, your website doesn't have a trackback, so for the benefit of the readers, there is a very good rebuttal here:
http://reason.com/blog/2010/10/19/battle-of-the-embarrassing-gra
Herbert Spencer . . . opposed all government aid to the poor and infirm . . .
Yes, that's true. . . . because it thwarted the biological law that the weakest should die. No, that's not right. It's fair to say that Spencer recognized the existence of a natural law that, as a matter of fact (not morality) caused the least fit (not necessarily "weakest") to die off or fail to reproduce, making room for more fit human beings. By "fitness" he meant pretty much what Darwin meant: adaptation to environment, whatever that environment may be. If the environment shields men from the consequences of folly, for example, it ends up filled with fools. If the environment is "militant," then the ruthless and strong survive. But Spencer believed that the modern world was moving away from a militant environment to a more peaceful one, based on productivity and trade. In the passage you quoted, I read Spencer saying that poor laws retard the evolution of human beings toward fitness for this new environment, thus prolonging the agony of transition. (This is even clearer if you read the preceding and following paragraphs.) Also, in a part you did not quote, he complains that poor laws, because they are administered so indiscriminately, cause people to adapt to living on the dole, rather than to producing: That careless squandering of pence which has fostered into perfection a system of organized begging--which has made skilful mendicancy more profitable than ordinary manual labour--which induces the simulation of palsy epilepsy, cholera, and no end of diseases and deformities which has called into existence warehouses for the sale and hire of impostor's dresses which has given to pity-inspiring babes a market value of 9d. per day--the unthinking benevolence which has generated all this cannot but be disapproved by every one. But this does not mean that Spencer objected to selective, voluntary charity: Now it is only against this injudicious charity that the foregoing argument tells. To that charity which may be described as helping men to help themselves, it makes no objection--countenances it rather. And in helping men to help themselves, there remains abundant scope for the exercise of a people's sympathies. Accidents will still supply victims on whom generosity may be legitimately expended. Men thrown upon their backs by unforeseen events, men who have failed for want of knowledge inaccessible to them, men ruined by the dishonesty of others, and men in whom hope long delayed has made the heart sick, may with advantage to all parties, be assisted. Even the prodigal, after severe hardship has branded his memory with the unbending conditions of social life to which he must submit, may properly have another trial afforded him. And although by these ameliorations the process of adaptation must be remotely interfered with, yet in the majority of cases it will not be so much retarded in one direction as it will be advanced in another. This hardly sounds like the "Social Darwinist" Spencer is often portrayed to have been.
Sidney Milkis' book on Theodore Roosevelt and the Progressive Party. (Milkis speech) addresses the issue of racism and the Progressive Party. The party conventions in the North were integrated, while those in the South were white-only. The Northern reformers had either to accept this or exclude those from the South who were "progressive" --
Post a Comment
"New South" proponents of a business- and industry-oriented economy -- the "young men on the make" Wilson referred to. The Northerners put up with it, hoping to change things later. (Jane Addams article) Instead, the race issue was one of the main reasons the party broke up in 1916. More seriously, it was one reason why Blacks did not support the party, which could have made the difference.
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |