Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts History, Neoconservatism, and Citizens United
|
Wednesday, January 27, 2010
History, Neoconservatism, and Citizens United
Step Feldman Four of the current Supreme Court justices can reasonably be characterized as displaying neoconservative tendencies (Thomas, Scalia, Roberts, and Alito). These justices joined with Kennedy to form the five-justice majority in Citizens United, which held that governmental limits on corporate (and union) spending for political campaign advertisements violate the first amendment. Did the Citizens United Court, therefore, apply neoconservative principles? Not if one understands the history of neoconservatism. A central component of neoconservatism as it developed in the 1950s, 1960s, and 1970s was its critique of the hegemonic pluralist democratic regime, which had taken hold of the nation in the 1930s. Pluralist democracy accepts ethical relativism: individuals and interest groups press their own interests and values in the democratic arena. From this array of competing interests and values, the government chooses to pursue those goals that emerge through certain established processes. No preexisting or higher principles limit the interests, values, and goals that can be urged. Process determines legitimacy. The early neoconservatives repudiated pluralist democracy and advocated for a return to republican democracy, which had predominated before the 1930s. Republican democratic theory holds that virtuous citizens and officials pursue the common good rather than their private interests. Thus, neocons rejected the ethical relativism that underlay the pluralist democratic regime and instead championed traditional American values or virtues that were to direct us toward the common good. Neoconservatism and Republican Democracy In The Closing of the American Mind, Allan Bloom drew inspiration from his teacher, Leo Strauss, the godfather of neoconservatism. Echoing Straussian themes, Bloom wrote: “The United States is one of the highest and most extreme achievements of the rational quest for the good life according to nature. What makes its political structure possible is the use of the rational principles of natural right to found a people, thus uniting the good with one’s own. Or, to put it otherwise, the regime established here promised untrammeled freedom to reason—not to everything indiscriminately, but [nonetheless] to reason.” When Bloom referred to “the regime established here,” he clearly was not denoting the post-World War II pluralist democratic regime built on relativism, historicism, and social-science empiricism. He was looking back to the republican democratic regime, which he equated with Strauss’s concept of the “best regime.” In this vein, Irving Kristol, a leading neocon, repeatedly invoked republican democratic principles. He encouraged Americans to recollect the nation’s original “revolutionary message.” The “founding fathers,” Kristol explained, “understood that republican self-government could not exist if humanity did not possess—at some moments, and to a fair degree—the traditional ‘republican virtues’ of self-control, self-reliance, and a disinterested concern for the public good.” But how can Americans cultivate civic republican virtue? We do so “through the shaping influence of religion, education, and [our] own daily experience.” That is, we must teach or inculcate virtue and then allow people to practice “self-government.” Neoconservatism and Free Speech Constitutional scholars have explored the ramifications of neoconservatism for free speech. Walter Berns, a political scientist who studied under Strauss and was Bloom’s faculty colleague at Cornell, published his first book, Freedom, Virtue, and the First Amendment, in 1957. Berns emphasized that, at the time, the predominant free-expression doctrine was the clear and present danger test. The justices, according to Berns, interpreted the clear and present danger test in the pluralist democratic regime to preclude courts, for the most part, from considering the content of speech and writing for purposes of first-amendment analysis. Except for cases involving national security, “speech of almost any character, true or false, good or bad, enjoys a favored status before the Court.” This approach supposedly followed from the modernist liberal (and social science) commitment to the fact-value dichotomy, which asserted that “all judgments of better and worse are arbitrary.” Berns denounced this judicial attempt to eschew value judgments regarding the content of expression. The “problem of free speech,” Berns explained, was really “the problem of virtue.” In resolving free-expression cases, the Court should attempt to “promote the virtue of citizens” and to pursue the “general welfare” (that is, the common good). Hence, Berns recommended the following: “Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom of good speech. The basic point is that the purpose of law is and must be to promote virtue, not to guarantee rights of any description.” This approach was the correlative equivalent, from a doctrinal standpoint, of the bad tendency test: the Court should allow the government to punish harmful or bad expression but should proscribe the government from punishing virtuous or good expression. In other words, Berns advocated for a return to a republican democratic approach to free expression; courts had applied the bad tendency test throughout the nineteenth and early-twentieth centuries. The Court must distinguish between “good and evil,” then must allow the government to shape, to educate, citizens of “good character” while censoring the licentious. Otherwise, the United States will be unable to protect “against dangers to civility” and will no longer be a “decent society.” The republican democratic focus on virtue and the common good was, to Berns, far more important than the pluralist democratic focus on the proper process: “The right [moral] education is ultimately much more decisive for good government, for free government, than any of the mechanical arrangements, such as the separation of powers, in which we Americans have traditionally placed our trust.” Ultimately, Berns insisted that all ideas are not equivalent and that all values are not relative. Despite the pretensions of pluralist democratic theorists, a civilized society cannot function if human relationships are based on nothing more than “calculating self-interest.” As citizens, we must proclaim our standards—we must distinguish good from evil—and we must then cultivate a good and virtuous society. And the justices need to do the same. Neoconservatism and Campaign Financing The Court in Citizens United reasoned that the statutory “prohibition on corporate independent expenditures is … a ban on speech.” Any “‘restriction on the amount of money a person or group can spend on political communication during a campaign’” implicates first-amendment protections. Thus, after linking the corporate expenditure of money with political expression, the Court emphasized the self-governance rationale, which accords near-absolute protection for political expression. “The right of citizens to inquire, to hear, to speak, and to use information to reach consensus is a precondition to enlightened self-government and a necessary means to protect it.” The early neocons did not explicitly discuss campaign finance restrictions. But Daniel Bell, a co-founder with Kristol in 1965 of the foremost neoconservative journal, The Public Interest, cautioned against the dangers of the modernist mixing of money and politics in pluralist democracy. In his 1976 book, The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism, Bell divided society into three realms: the techno-economic (or social), the cultural, and the political. The three realms, he suggested, will contribute to a stable society if they either remain separate or operate in ways that reinforce each other. For instance, early in the development of capitalism, a culture of hard work, self-discipline, and self-denial—characterized by Max Weber as the Protestant ethic—bolstered the capitalist economy by encouraging individuals to devote themselves to employment in bureaucratically organized workplaces. By the second half of the twentieth century, however, the three realms overlapped and intersected in ways that were not mutually reinforcing; rather, they contradicted each other, causing societal instability. The main contradiction of modern life, according to Bell, was between the capitalist economy and the modernist culture, which imbued individuals with a hedonistic desire for self-gratification. “In the world of capitalist enterprise, the nominal ethos in the spheres of production and organization is still one of work, delayed gratification, career orientation, devotion to the enterprise. Yet, on the marketing side, the sale of goods, packaged in the glossy images of glamour and sex, promotes a hedonistic way of life whose promise is the voluptuous gratification of the lineaments of desire. The consequence of this contradiction … is that a corporation finds its people being straight by day and swingers by night.” Bell also accentuated tensions between the economic and political realms. The operative principle of the capitalist economy was efficiency, maximizing one’s benefits while minimizing costs, while the operative principle of the pluralist democratic polity in post-World War II America was equality, requiring that all individuals be “able to participate fully” as citizens. If the two realms had remained distinct, each could successfully fulfill its respective principle. But the two realms bled into each other, Bell argued, thus producing discordance. For example, aiming for efficiency, capitalism relied on hierarchically structured bureaucratic organizations that collided with the political desire for participatory equality. Moreover, as the two realms intermingled, an increasing number of issues, previously settled in the capitalist marketplace, shifted into the political realm. Consequently, instead of being decided pursuant to “technocratic rationality” leading to economic efficiency, they were (and are) resolved through a political “bargaining” process that facilitates participation. Economic decisions, therefore, were (and are) made for the wrong reasons. This problem was greatly exacerbated, according to Bell, because the modernist culture of self-gratification induced individuals and societal groups to express an ever-increasing number of excessive demands within the political realm. Demands for equal participation gave way to demands for “rising entitlements,” including “a basic minimum family income,” a minimal “standard of living,” and so on. These never-ending demands then generated group conflict and societal instability. Originalism, Republican Democracy, and Free Speech Neoconservative (and other conservative) constitutional scholars often advocate for an originalist approach to constitutional interpretation. Walter Berns, for one, lamented how the post-1937 Court eschewed republican democratic principles. “[T]he constitutional law of the [post-1937] First Amendment has not been built on the precedents and principles of the past,” Berns wrote. “One looks almost in vain for references in the Court’s opinions to what the great [nineteenth century] commentators—Story, Kent, and Cooley, for example—have written on freedom of speech and religion, or to what the Founders intended with the First Amendment.” Strict adherence to originalism and neoconservative principles would support a doctrinal approach akin to the bad tendency test, which predominated during the republican democratic regime. The return of the bad tendency test would allow the government to punish any speech or writing that had likely harmful consequences or that might be deemed antithetical to a virtuous citizenry and the common good. Significantly, the self-governance rationale, which the Citizens United Court invoked, rose to prominence only after the post-1937 judicial acceptance of pluralist democracy. The crux of pluralist democracy is free and open citizen participation; if citizens cannot express their interests and values, then such participation seems impossible. Free expression thus appears to be a precondition for the pluralist democratic process itself—hence, the near-absolute protection for political expression. For this reason, governmental limitations on corporate expenditures for political campaigns are constitutionally problematic (though not necessarily unconstitutional). But if the Court were to follow an originalist and neoconservative approach, a governmental limitation on corporate campaign expenditures could be readily justified as promoting the common good. Under republican democracy, the right to free expression—even for political speech and writing—always remained subordinate to the common good. Thus, speech and writing could potentially be restricted in many situations. Specifically, the government could act to preserve the integrity of the democratic process by limiting corporate campaign expenditures without violating the first amendment, regardless of whether the corporate expenditures were categorized as speech itself or as merely facilitating speech. Stephen M. Feldman Jerry W. Housel/Carl F. Arnold Distinguished Professor of Law and Adjunct Professor of Political Science, University of Wyoming Posted 1:33 AM by Step Feldman [link]
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |