Balkinization  

Friday, September 18, 2009

The Necessity and Peril of Ethical History

Guest Blogger

For The Constitution in 2020 Conference, October 2-4, 2009 at Yale Law School. Crossposted at The Constitution in 2020 blog.

Richard Primus

Distinguish three forms of historical argument in constitutional theory: as positive authority, as practical experience, and as national ethos.

(1) History deployed as positive authority purports to settle the meaning of clauses or doctrines by reference to things that happened in the past. For example, the way language was commonly used in 1789 might be adduced to establish the meaning of “religion” in the First Amendment, and the practices of many different states over time might be adduced to determine whether a particular liberty is fundamental for the purposes of substantive due process.

(2) History deployed as practical experience aims to help decisionmakers translate normative constitutional visions into effective institutional arrangements. It might point out that something taken as necessary is actually contingent; or that something regarded as happenstance has resisted numerous attempts at change; or that different institutions have had differing success in pursuing certain goals; or that an axiom of constitutional wisdom may be an inherited bromide rather than a cogent analysis of how government operates.

(3) History deployed as national ethos attempts to tell a story about the constitutional values of the American People. We are a people who prize democracy, or federalism, or who fought a terrible Civil War to end slavery, or whose institutions presuppose a Supreme Being.

Of these three forms of argument, history as national ethos is often the most powerful. It sometimes comes cloaked as one of the other kinds: many historical arguments that seem to sound in positive authority or practical experience are better understood as sounding in ethos. They do their work if they persuade their audiences to accept not just the particular historical propositions for which they are offered but a general and value-laden impression about the meaning of American history. Much originalist argument is best understood as argument about national ethos, inasmuch as it attempts to portray a heroic American constitutional past that supports a particular set of value choices in the present. Much of what we call “redemptive constitutionalist interpretation” similarly deploys history as ethos.

Successful movements in constitutional politics are good at making historical arguments that sound in national ethos. I hope that in the year 2020 progressives will stand securely on their versions of the national ethos in the sphere of constitutional politics. But there is a danger here for scholars who are attracted to the arena of those politics.

Because American history can be narrated in several different ways that highlight different (and conflicting) values, the interpreter who deploys history as ethos will privilege some values and shunt others aside. The choice can be made with varying levels of self-awareness, but the narrative offered will always be partial and contestable. Making those choices is an appropriate activity in politics, including constitutional politics. But such simplifications are dangerous to the spirit of scholarship, which should embrace complexity rather than repressing it away. Accordingly, constitutional theorists who work in the academy should beware of presenting their ethical narratives as—to use a phrase advisedly—the law.
This does not mean that good scholarship should not be normative. It means only that the normativity appropriate to scholarship must be consistent with rendering the world in its complexity. Where the dominant historical narrative supports undesirable constitutional politics, it is appropriate for scholars to showcase alternatives, thus pointing out that the world is complex and that the dominant narrative is not a necessary framing. In that spirit, I have previously recommended the development of “mobilizable history” beyond what is conventionally made the source of constitutional argument. But constitutional theory—or at least academic constitutional theory—should remain aware that any alternative narratives are also partial. And public officials should strive to remember that complexity when making constitutional decisions now, in 2020, and beyond.


Older Posts
Newer Posts
Home