Balkinization |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahman sabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Critical Reflections on Leiter's "Naturalistic Jurisprudence"
|
Tuesday, December 09, 2008
Critical Reflections on Leiter's "Naturalistic Jurisprudence"
Brian Tamanaha Chicago law professor Brian Leiter is widely known for his various blogs, but he is also a serious legal philosopher who has staked out a unique position within the field. For more than a decade, he has advocated “Naturalizing Jurisprudence” (The essays developing his view are collected here.) Leiter explains that by “naturalism” he means "a methodological doctrine about how we should approach philosophical inquiry. On this view, philosophy proceeds (as the most familiar metaphor has it) ‘in tandem with the sciences,’ that is, as the abstract and reflective branch of the empirical sciences as they limn the causal structure of the world.” Leiter agues that legal philosophers ought to adopt this naturalistic approach to philosophical questions about law, which promises to be more fruitful than current conceptual or normative inquiries. Jurists who engage in socio-legal theory (or “sociological jurisprudence”), as I do, would seem to be natural allies for Leiter’s approach. But there appears to be a difference between these endeavors. Broadly speaking, sociological jurisprudence assumes a thoroughly social view of law, and draws from social science to inform theorizing about law. It is less a discrete field of study than an umbrella that encompasses theoretical work on law with a strongly empirical orientation. Leiter’s arguments, while sharing some of the same assumptions, are pitched in a different direction: his arguments are directed at other legal philosophers, in effect telling them they are engaged in misdirected abstract inquiries that amount to little more than dressing up their intuitions in fancy philosophical clothes. I’ll let legal philosophers fight that battle (although my view is that there is value in all kinds of theory). Instead, I thought it might be informative to examine Leiter’s arguments from the standpoint of someone already committed to sociological jurisprudence. A few critical observations about the potential pitfalls of Leiter’s naturalized jurisprudence follow after the break. In a recent paper, Leiter offers three examples of how one might “naturalize jurisprudential questions.” I will take up only the first example here, as that will suffice to articulate my concerns about his approach. The following is a full paragraph that sets out his core argument on the first example, although I take the liberty of splitting the paragraph and injecting a clarifying comment. Leiter writes: [A] naturalized jurisprudence might ask what must law be if current social-scientific theory of adjudication (namely, the Attitudinal Model) is to be true and explanatory? For the Attitudinal Model to be true and explanatory, there has to be, among other things, a clear demarcation between the ideological attitudes of judges (which are causally effective in determining the decisions) and the valid sources of law which are central to the Legal Model’s competing explanation of judicial decisions. Thus, implicit in the Attitudinal Model is quite plainly a concept of law as exhausted by authoritative texts (precedents, statutes, constitutions) which are the raw material of the competing Legal Model, and which exclude the ideological attitudes central to the Attitudinal Model. The reasoning in this paragraph (split in two parts by me) strikes me as problematic in crucial ways that illustrate the risks of Leiter’s enterprise. Leiter brings together philosophical arguments and social science arguments in ways that misshapes both, making strange moves and coming to a strange conclusion. My critical examination will focus on just three steps (numbered). 1. First, it is essential to note that the inquiry Leiter begins with is awkwardly framed: “what must law be if [the Attitudinal Model] is true and explanatory?” By framing it this way, which he does for philosophical reasons tied to naturalism, Leiter interjects theoretical points that have no place in the social scientific inquiry at issue. The Attitudinal Model is a simplified model that political scientists rely upon to design and structure studies of judicial decision making. The basic idea behind the model is the assumption that judges decide cases oriented toward achieving their political preferences, with the law serving mainly as a constraint. If the results of a given study bear out the model to a high degree of confidence (reaching statistical significance and actual significance), then it “explains” the decisions. What makes Leiter’s statement odd is that social scientists would never think to ask “what must law be [if the model is true and explanatory]?” For social scientists, the “explanatory” value of the model is confirmed (or not) by the results of study. Social scientists are not immediately concerned with the assumptions their model makes about law, but with whether the model produces a reliable account of judicial decision making. They are trying to isolate on and test the causal connection between the personal preferences of judges and their legal decisions. These comments merely point out that social scientists and philosophers are engaged in different inquires, which is to be expected, but the following two points show how the failure to pay close attention to this leads to mistakes. 2. Several basic points must be made about the Attitudinal Model and the Legal Model. They are both simplified models for the purposes of research design. The idea behind this starkly posed contrast is to test whether judges decide cases in accordance with the law (legal model) or in accordance with their personal preferences (attitudinal model). Political scientists understand that judging is more complex than either model implies, but the contrast is useful nonetheless. (It should be mentioned that the Strategic Model is perhaps the hottest version within the field today, but Leiter does not mention it, so I will leave it out. It is worth noting in passing, however, that Leiter’s philosophical analysis relies heavily on the binary contrast between the legal and attitudinal models, whereas the strategic model involves a more nuanced integration of the two.) Here is the crucial move Leiter makes when moving from the social science inquiry to the philosophical inquiry: he transforms the assumptions of their simplified model into what is “quite plainly a concept of law as exhausted by authoritative texts.” Following this reasoning, Leiter goes on to assert that the Legal Model is “vindicated” by Raz’s Hard Legal Positivism. The vast chasm that separates these respective inquiries bears emphasis: Although researchers have constructed a simplified legal model to contrast with a simplified attitudinal model, social scientists, Leiter tells us, implicitly made far more profound claims: they implicitly relied upon a “concept of law,” and this concept of law is none other than Raz’s legal positivism (a controversial theory of law within legal philosophy). Leiter suggests that this complementary match lends gravitas to the model, as well as credibility to Raz’s hard legal positivism Two related points will be made against his arguments. First, it is a supreme stretch to assert that a simplified model of judging makes any claim at all, implicitly or otherwise, about a “concept of law.” It can be said that these two alternative models make assertions about law and judging, but these are merely posited assumptions for the purposes of the study. To call this a “concept of law” gives it a standing and makes an additional set of claims that are not entailed within the notion of a “model.” Leiter knows that the social scientists using these models do not explicitly claim to be producing a concept of law, but he seems to be arguing that legal philosophers can extract one anyway. What Leiter fails to recognize, however, is that there are different formulations of the Legal Model; indeed almost every study that tests the Legal Model posits a different set of assumptions about what the model requires. That’s why it is hazardous to assert that the Legal Model adopts any particular concept of law. Even if one grants Leiter’s leap from a model to a concept of law for the sake of argument, secondly, it is wrong to assert that the Legal Model necessarily adopts Raz’s hard positivism rather than some other competing concept of law (like, for example, Soft or Inclusive legal positivism, a major rival of Raz’s position). A deep lesson about the perils of his project lies in this objection: Leiter has drawn his erroneous conclusion because he confuses the social scientific question with the legal philosophy debate. They sound similar, but they are not. Leiter’s mistake can be made plain in connection with his assertion that the Legal Model “excludes the ideological attitudes central to the Attitudinal Model.” Let’s assume that this is correct; the point remains that excluding the “ideological attitudes” of judges is very different from excluding “moral inquiries” in legal analysis. Leiter treats these in some sense as equivalent, or he appears to assume that the former entails the latter, but they are distinct. (I am reconstructing Leiter's argument here because he does not actually explain his reasoning on this point.) Hard legal positivism precludes moral inquiries, and Leiter appears to take that to be the key that links the Legal Model to hard positivism, but the Legal Model cares about political preferences. A range of theories of law that do not exclude moral inquiry nonetheless assert that judges should not be influenced by their personal preferences when engaging in such inquiry (the assumption of the legal model); these theories of law, accordingly, are also consistent with the Legal Model. This point will be demonstrated in connection with Raz's main rival--inclusive legal positivism. Drastically simplified, here is the core difference between these theories: inclusive legal positivists assert that questions of law can turn on moral inquiries (when the rule of recognition provides for it), whereas hard positivists insist that what is valid law must not depend upon a judge answering moral questions (but is a matter of pedigree). The Legal Model can easily accept the notion within Inclusive Legal Positivism that the law may require judges to make moral decisions (nor does this matter for the Attitudinal Model). For example, let’s say that open-ended legal questions (fairness, reasonableness, cruel and unusual) require the judge to decide based upon the community’s moral views of these issues. The Legal Model says nothing at all about this one way or the other; all it says is that judges should not be influenced by personal preferences when making legal decisions. If the law requires these types of open inquiries, there is no problem; fidelity to law by judges in their decisions can be tested by either the Attitudinal or Legal Models. Here is an example: A given study might find that a liberal judge deciding cases with open-ended questions of this sort makes decisions that correlate to a high degree with conservative political outcomes; presumably the explanation for this pattern would be that those outcomes are consistent with the moral view of the community (as distinct from the judge's moral views) that the law incorporates. These decisions, which can turn on the judge findings answers to moral questions, would not be influenced by personal preferences (This example is not far fetched because studies show that on many issues liberal judges rule more often in a conservative than a liberal direction). In this example, the judge would decide in a fashion contrary to what the Attitudinal Model predicts, lending support for the Legal Model. But these results--and the models they test--have no bearing at all on any philosophical theory of law. The bottom line is that the Legal Model does not necessarily endorse hard positivism—or indeed any other concept of law—because the assumptions of the Legal Model are consistent with a range of theories of law. A model or account of how judges judge (whether they are influenced by personal values) is different from a theory of law, and can align with the latter in various ways. 3. The strangest part of Leiter’s argument comes at the end: “…Hard Positivism, in short, captures what law must be if the Attitudinal Model is true and explanatory….for the naturalist it suffices that the Hard Positivist concept of law figures in the best explanatory account of legal phenomena. I won’t repeat earlier objections to this line of reasoning but instead will point out how this conclusion twists matters into a logical pretzel. For social scientists, because these two models are often set out as competing explanations, the confirmation of the attitudinal model—a demonstration that it is “true or explanatory”—often entails the refutation or diminishment of the legal model. But Leiter obscures this antipodal relationship, reasoning that the hard positivist concept of law (embodied in the Legal Model) must be correct “if the Attitudinal Model is true and explanatory.” That is a weird way of describing matters. The vindication of the Attitudinal Model by social scientists brings down the competing Legal Model, whereas for Leiter the Attitudinal Model is true if the concept of law that the Legal Model is based upon (or so he asserts) is true. Leiter thus claims the concept of law purportedly vindicated by the Legal Model is “true and explanatory” even when the model does poorly in the social scientist’s actual study. The actual results of the study, in other words, don’t mean anything for Leiter’s philosophical point. There is a consistent logic to Leiter’s reasoning, but it strains common sense, and has great potential for confusion. Ultimately Leiter backs away from this argument, noting that the attitudinal model has relatively weak predictive power. So he does not go further with this particular analysis. It is offered by him as an example how how a naturalized jurisprudence might work. And that is the way it should be understood. The problem, what I hope to have demonstrated in this lengthy post, is that it is dangerous to translate social scientific inquiries into inquires in legal philosophy. They have different interests and concerns that are not easy to translate. Nothing in this post refutes Leiter’s philosophical argument for naturalizing jurisprudence (which I do not address), but legal philosophers who follow his lead must tread with caution. Posted 12:10 PM by Brian Tamanaha [link]
Comments:
Brian,
I'm slogging through this one, easily the most enjoyable post here in ages. I got this far: "...[Leiter] confuses the social scientific question with the legal philosophy debate. They sound similar, but they are not." At the risk of sounding catty, I would probably restate that as, "Philosophy of late seeks to gain some small sense of relevancy by appropriating themes from other pursuits." Professor Leiter is brilliant, but legal philosophy seems purely an ivory tower pursuit most of the time.
Professor Tamanaha was kind enough to e-mail me about his post. I am afraid his comments betray some fairly significant misunderstandings and confusions about the philosophical issues and the actual arguments. I do hope interested readers (who can bear with the "ivory tower pursuit" that is, as Mr. Link suspects, central to much legal philosophy) will take a look at the linked essay. I am under some deadlines, but I will return with a more substantive response by the weekend.
Between visits from the likes of Professor Leiter and thoughts of lurkers ala Professor Levinson's recent post, I begin to wonder about the wisdom of my generally jocular approach to this blog comments business.
Leiter's references are to formal not empirical science. But language is a medium, like paint, or clay, while numbers are seen by most as Platonic: not as representations but as the foundation of the world.
A philosophy that sees the structure of language as replicating the structure of the world renders the sociological study of language production of secondary interest. Leiter's naturalism is the naturalism of Quine, not Santayana. Yet Santayana's terms apply, all too well. Arguing for a philosophy ‘in tandem with the sciences,’ Leiter nonetheless admits philosophy is not a science, leaving us to assume that the relation of the two must be like the Nietzschean relation of the best of modern men to absent gods: one of sympathetic vibration. Leiter's philosophy is based in fact on little more than romantic analogies, of philosophy to science and philosopher to scientist, that foster an insular formalism and champion a model of academic hierarchy as immune to criticism from outside its walls as the 11th century Church. I know of no other self-proclaimed leftist so utterly contemptuous of democracy. Again: Language does not describe the world; it is a medium through which we describe to one another our perceptions of it. It is a medium. Numbers are not. Naturalist epistemology in language proceeds only by analogy to the "natural epistemology" of number. And analogy is a rhetorical device.
This is something I actually agree with Leiter on. If by naturalizing jurisprudence he means that social scientists should be left in charge rather than theoretical-philosophers, what is there is argue?
Post a Comment
I guess you're not arguing this, as the last couple of lines might suggest? I wish those had appeared earlier on in the essay. http://reaching-oblivion.blogspot.com/
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers ![]() Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) ![]() David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) ![]() Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). ![]() Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). ![]() Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) ![]() Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) ![]() Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) ![]() Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) ![]() Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) ![]() Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) ![]() Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) ![]() Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution ![]() Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) ![]() Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) ![]() Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) ![]() Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) ![]() James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) ![]() Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) ![]() Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) ![]() Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) ![]() Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) ![]() Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) ![]() Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic ![]() Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) ![]() Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) ![]() Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) ![]() Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) ![]() David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) ![]() Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) ![]() Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) ![]() Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |