Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts Why the sex discrimination argument failed in California
|
Friday, May 23, 2008
Why the sex discrimination argument failed in California
Andrew Koppelman
It remains puzzling why the California Supreme Court, in its recent same-sex marriage decision, rejected the most formally powerful argument for its result: the argument that denying licenses to same-sex couples is sex discrimination. The weakness is made clear in this recent column by Steve Chapman, who writes: “while the California Constitution forbids discrimination on the basis of ‘sex, race, creed, color, or national or ethnic origin,’ it does not forbid discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation. The justices somehow found something in the document that the authors thought they omitted.” As I’ve explained earlier, the Court had to work very hard to reject the sex discrimination argument, using tired old arguments that had been used long ago to defend miscegenation laws: since both blacks and whites [both men and women] are equally burdened, there’s no discrimination.
Comments:
Because the court never said that people should have the same rights with a woman that they do with a man. It's entirely appropriate for people to have the right to conceive with someone of the opposite sex but not with someone of the same sex.
John:
That reasoning would be relevant if the law at issue were one that prohibited a man from conceiving a baby using the eggs of another man. But since the law at issue prohibits two men from getting married, and says nothing one way or the other about conceiving children, your argument is irrelevant.
I, as a gay libertarian, have always found the "it's not sex discrimination" thesis to be the one and only talking point against gay marriage that is totally reasonable and utterly inoffensive.
Straight men and straight women are treated equally (i.e., better than gays). Gay men and gay women are treated equally (i.e., worse than straights). That is simply not sex discrimination. Meanwhile, note that California's anti-miscegenation law did NOT treat the races equally: Blacks could marry, e.g., Asians, Hispanics and American Indians. Whites could only marry other whites (see Page 86 of the decision). If you (correctly) rephrase the anti-miscegenation law as "no white may marry a non-white," then the fallacy of the "symmetry" argument becomes self-apparent. That is another reason why gay marriage is better rooted in the anti-miscegenation invalidations than in sex discrimination claims.
Right Dilan, but the court is leaving open the possibility that such a law could be written. Conceiving children is one of the rights of marriage, so a law like that would be incompatible. Also, the court doesn't want to say that same-sex couples should have equal rights to a man and a woman, even if the right in question has nothing to do with marriage. Like maybe it has to do with public bathrooms or health clubs or social clubs, which are based on the right to do something in the presence of other people being distinct depending on the sex of the other people present. If there are no other people present, it wouldn't be an issue what sex you were.
Professor Koppelman,
I think this has a lot to do with the politics of recognition. As you and others have persuasively pointed out, anti-gay discrimination is sex discrimination. With marriage restrictions, where A could marry B but for A's sex, that's just more obvious than usual. But that route to recognition suffers not only from being 'unfamiliar,' as you note, but also from seeming to many gay people to fail to acknowledge their group as an equally important, separate, distinctive group, with its own growing social movement, deserving of its own special category of protection like race and sex, not via sex. I think that a lot of what is going on here is that the court is trying to formulate the core logic of the decision in such a way that it focuses on recognition for the group, and the social movement, whose push for equality is what got us here. (Of course, why so many gay people believe, wrongly in my view, that their struggle has nothing to do with sex discrimination, would take a much longer discussion! I would love to hear your thoughts on it.)
In the world I live in, whether a man can conceive a child with another man simply isn't an issue of law or constitutional rights.
where was the snark? Did you think "eggs from another man" was a joke? If only! Dude - google "female sperm" or "same-sex conception" and then re-read the CA decision in light of the question of whether to allow that or not.
Why is it "puzzling" that CA, as was the case in various court rulings and civil rights laws ... and general societal understanding ... focused on the more well recognized/accepted route?
The comparison to Loving only takes one so far. There is clearly a "homosexual" group here, right? Formulating some group of those (by birth? etc.) attracted to the opposite race is less sensible, if possible. Again, why exactly is this so confusing? Now, I realize the force of the gender discrimination argument. But, like those who wanted Roe to go that route, it really isn't currently a realistic path given the situation. The force of the argument makes the dismissal in that part of the opinion messy. Lawrence suggested equality might be a route, but argued it was prudent to take due process. Other rulings ignore secondary arguments as not necessary, given they were decided on other grounds. I'm not sure why CA felt obligated to (messily) dismiss the gender route. But, I'm not "puzzled" why it focused elsewhere. [btw, even if Virginia was consistent and didn't allow Asians to marry blacks, or whatever, the law would be unconstitutional; but that wrinkle does complicate things]
Laws against same-sex marriage prohibit both homosexuals and heterosexuals from marrying a person of the same sex. Hence these laws treat homosexuals and heterosexuals equally and hence do not discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation.
Laws against same-sex marriage prohibit both homosexuals and heterosexuals from marrying a person of the same sex. Hence these laws treat homosexuals and heterosexuals equally and hence do not discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation.
Likewise, laws against polygamy prohibit both monogamists and polygamists from practicing polygamy. Hence these laws treat monogamists and polygamists equally and hence do not discriminate on the basis of marital status. I hope you were either joking or drinking when you came up with this bulletproof logic.
It seems pretty natural to argue that a ban on miscegenation did not provide substantive racial equality, but that the "mandatory miscegenation" of different-sex marriage laws does. The best argument would be that the inequality in this case is purely formal, which doesn't seem that unreasonable to me. You can find a few feminist theorists somewhere who will argue that different-sex-only marriage is really about keeping women down but this is very much a fringe view and it's not surprising the courts aren't interested in going for it.
You are, of course, entirely right about discrimination against gays and lesbians being about gender norms, but the courts haven't been terribly interested in finding that requiring people to adhere to gender norms is impermissible sex discrimination. Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins did go for the plaintiff, but my understanding is that it hasn't been much expanded. Different dress expectations for men and women are still legal and their constitutionality is not in doubt.
men keeping women down or women keeping men down, but sexual reproduction keeping the genetic engineers down. And yes, sexual reproduction, in our species, does divide humanity into humans with wombs that get pregnant and humans that don't have wombs that impregnate them.
The question is, do we preserve that system to preserve male superiority or female superiority or because it is a pretty good efficient system with a lot going for it, and much better than the alternatives? The alternatives are expensive and require lots of regulation and government and will become huge entitlements, even requirements. They won't even guarantee that men and women will be more equal, not with women only able to produce girls and men not having wombs of their own. Perhaps not needing each other to reproduce will make things worse rather than better. And anyway, at a time when millions of people are without adequate nutrition and basic health care and our energy use is obscenely excessive, pursuing alternatives to sexual reproduction are also unethical. Plus, pursuing them will change the way we view children and equality and the other sex. It is good that we all have to cooperate with someone of the other sex to reproduce. It is good that it doesn't use any electricity to do it. It is good that the process causes us to view all people as equals because we were all created the same way, by a man's sperm fertilizing a woman's egg, without any tinkering.
"They won't even guarantee that men and women will be more equal, not with women only able to produce girls and men not having wombs of their own."
I rather doubt that women who are determined not even to use sperm donors are going to be too put out over not being able to give birth to males. And I fully expect we'll have artificial wombs within a decade or so. So the men WILL have wombs of their own, they'll buy them out of a catalog! (Just like many of the women, once they're proven out.)
right, already, lesbian couples overwhelmingly choose to have girls when sex selection is available, so most will not mind that they will only be able to have girls. Artificial wombs might indeed make men and women more equal, but that couldn't be achieved until all babies were born from them, and no women still had their own wombs, and even then, it still might not be achieved, there still might be inequalities that remain or that even are heightened.
My point remains: as a method to achieve equality of men and women and eliminate any "system of supremacy" for either sex or orientation, the idea of same-sex conception is really dubious and dumb. Postgenderist" Feminists have implied that women won't be free until women are free from their biological role as mothers, but again, we don't know that it will work, and there are other ways to achieve a better result. Marriage is the better way to achieve a better result, where one male and one female pair up for life and spiritually and legally become one flesh, for life, sharing bed and hearth. (note the argument against polygamy inherent in this reason for marriage).
@ PMS_Chicago:
[Larry Fafarman]: Laws against same-sex marriage prohibit both homosexuals and heterosexuals from marrying a person of the same sex. Hence these laws treat homosexuals and heterosexuals equally and hence do not discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation. Likewise, laws against polygamy prohibit both monogamists and polygamists from practicing polygamy. Hence these laws treat monogamists and polygamists equally and hence do not discriminate on the basis of marital status. Likewise, laws against miscegenation prohibit both blacks and whites from marrying someone of the other race. Both races are perfectly free to marry; they may marry someone of their own race, but are equally prohibited from marrying someone of the opposite race. Neither race is disadvantaged. That argument went over well in Loving.... Cheers,
John, being a libertarian rather than an egalitarian, I'm not particularly concerned with making men and women more "equal", I'd rather just make both more free.
well, Brett, allowing same-sex conception won't even make people more free. First of all, same-sex couples will feel coerced to use it as soon as it is offered. It'll just be a question of if they can afford it. And then, because it would open the door to allowing all forms of genetic modification, it would lead to all people feeling coerced to use enhanced or at least screened gametes, because it will be seen as unethical to use natural gametes. It won't be too long before people are not allowed to use natural gametes, it could actually be a crime. At first it will seem like a new option is being offered, but look further down that road and you'll see that it isn't freedom at all.
"First of all, same-sex couples will feel coerced to use it as soon as it is offered."
Being a libertarian, I also have little interest in arguments that people are coerced by having more options, so we ought to 'free' them by restricting the options available to them. Sorry, that's at best nonsense. You can claim that we'll inevitably lose our reproductive liberty as a result of genetic engineering being used on humans, but the only person I see attacking that liberty right now is YOU.
There's a principle called "procreative beneficence" that operates on everyone's moral beliefs which causes people to choose everything offered to them in order to have the "best possible child". It is almost like not having a choice at all. It's like having the choice to drink during pregnancy, sure, some will choose to, but most people feel obligated to quit drinking, and people get mighty upset at anyone they see drinking while pregnant.
And it's not only me, most other countries have banned germline GE, it's only a few psycho countries that are pursuing it. I don't know what is so wrong with the US that so many people here think we should be intervening in the process of people having babies, I think it is a form of guilt.
This reminds me of an old joke.
Post a Comment
Three men walk into a bar. The bartender asks the first man, "What'll you have?" The guy responds, "I'll have a beer." The bartender nods and gets the guy a beer. He turns to the second guy. "What about you, buddy?" The second guy thinks for a second and says, "I'll have a shot of whiskey." "You bet," says the bartender, and he gives the guy a shot of whiskey. "And you? What's your poison?" the bartender asked the third guy. Without batting an eye, the guy responds, "It won't be too long before people are not allowed to use natural gametes; it could actually be a crime!"
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |