Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts What is Living Constitutionalism?
|
Thursday, March 27, 2008
What is Living Constitutionalism?
JB
This past week I've written a couple of posts that offer an account of living constitutionalism, in which popular mobilization and partisan entrenchment in the judiciary play a major role in shaping constitutional change. This version of living constitutionalism is also a "democratic constitutionalism." (I borrow this term from my colleagues Robert Post and Reva Siegel). It is "living" constitutionalism is because judicial and non judicial interpretations change over time, and it is "democratic" because they change in response to sustained social and political mobilizations that, in turn alter constitutional culture. Last week Dahlia Litwick and Eric Posner offered their comments on this model, and today I offer a further elaboration.
Comments:
"As many of you know, I regard myself as both an originalist and a living constitutionalist."
This seems to answer a question I have posed to JB in earlier comments. So JB sits atop the constitutional fence with his "mug" (originalist) on one side and his "wamp" (living constitutionalist) on the other. Perhaps a hermeneutical overlay might be appropriate for the this "Mugwamp" version of living-originalism.
Professor Balkin:
Living constitutionalism is primarily a theory about what makes the process that produces changing interpretations of the Constitution legitimate. It appears to me that your views of both living constitutionalism and originalism are designed to legitimatize decisions which would otherwise be illegitimate under what most theorists consider originalism. A theory of "originalism" that abandons the original understanding of the text, expands the current meaning of the text to principles broad enough to encompass nearly anything (such as a 14th Amendment right to kill one's children) and allows interpretations of those principles to change significantly over time cannot fairly be called originalism, which requires a fidelity to a meaning fixed at the time of the ratification of a constitutional provision. While one can fairly argue over the best means to determine the meaning fixed at the time of the ratification, originalism requires a fixed original meaning if the term originalism is to have any meaning at all.
Unfortunately, Bart, your account of what originalism must mean isn't the original meaning of originalism.
Your use of the phrase "vector sum of political forces" reminded me of my favorite analogy for the restraining (you called them "supermajoritarian") features of our system. I think of them as slosh baffles that prevent hysterical crowds from tramping individuals.
How about "Original Sin Originalism" along the lines of Genesis to explain away the intent, meaning, understanding, expectations, etc, of the Constitution? That would be simply divine.
Professor Balkin:
Unfortunately, Bart, your account of what originalism must mean isn't the original meaning of originalism. Which is?
Unfortunately, Bart, your account of what originalism must mean isn't the original meaning of originalism.
Which is? Original intent?
Unfortunately, Bart, your account of what originalism must mean isn't the original meaning of originalism.
Which is? Bart, let me give you some idea of where Professor Balkin is coming from. I first encountered him long before this blog, when I read "The Crystalline Structure of Legal Thought" in law school about a decade and a half ago. The man has been seriously researching legal theory and producing peer-reviewed scholarship in major law journals for many, many years. You might, Bart, at some point admit that he might know a little more about what originalism does and doesn't mean, and what it's theorists do and don't claim, than you do. It isn't like you are publishing in the law reviews. (As someone who, in addition to his legal work, has published a few articles in major law reviews, I can tell you that it requires a rigor that you do not bring to this issue when you talk about originalism in the same sorts of simplistic terminology ("interpreting the Constitution as written instead of inventing new rights", "14th Amendment right to kill one's children") that Rush Limbaugh and Sean Hannity might use. Bart, Professor Balkin has a lot to tell you about originalism. And if you don't buy his arguments, you can look at the work of conservative scholars who also treat the subject seriously rather than using "living constitutionalism" as an epithet for whatever results they don't like. I would suggest, however, that you not opine beyond your expertise, that you not go beyond your remit. You are badly overmatched when taking on someone who has been around the scholarly block as many times as Professor Balkin has on this issue.
dilan:
The fact that Professor Balkin and I may disagree is neither here nor there. I offered the common definition of originalism as the theory that the meaning of provisions of the Constitution is knowable and fixed at the origin of the document. Professor Balkin claimed that originalism actually has a quite different definition without providing that definition. I am simply asking for the contrary definition. No matter how learned my correspondent, I do not accept bare assertions as undisputed fact.
No matter how learned my correspondent, I do not accept bare assertions as undisputed fact.
Why, I have that very same tendency. In fact, when that correspondent miscites actual law, I'm even a bit more sceptical and ask for substantiation (and corrections as appropriate). However, not everyone here bothers to back up their assertions, even when asked repeatedly for such. In fact, a few of the more impolite ones just go on and reassert the same stuff in the next post down the line again without substantiation.... OBTW, there's a link in Prof. Balkin's point under that "originalist" blue clicky... (documentation and substantiation of my above assertions available on request, of course) Cheers,
I offered the common definition of originalism as the theory that the meaning of provisions of the Constitution is knowable and fixed at the origin of the document.
Bart, is that the common definition as put forth by Robert Bork? The common definition as put forth by Antonin Scalia? The common definition as put forth by Akhil Reed Amar? The common definition as put forth by Hugo Black? By critics like John Hart Ely or Paul Brest? Randy Barnett? Could you summarize what the differences are between those various authors' conceptions of originalism? If I may paraphrase a great legal thinker, originalism isn't a brooding omnipresence in the sky. It is a category that includes various interpretative metrics. Indeed, some of the interpretative metrics included in originalism definitely do not believe that the meaning of the Constitution is fixed at the origin of the document. Not even Scalia, for instance, believes that. (See his majority opinion on thermal imaging.) Nor does Bork. (See his discussion of libel law in "The Tempting of America" and his wiretapping decision on the DC Circuit.) What you are offering, Bart, is a radio talk show definition of originalism, used by right-wing hacks to claim that liberal theories of jurisprudence are unprincipled when compared to conservative theories of jurisprudence. You show no signs of having actually engaged the deep jurisprudential debates about text and meaning. Ever heard of H.L.A. Hart? "No vehicles in the park"? Those of us who have studied some of this stuff know that it is a fascinating and complex subject matter. Real interpretation is HARD, and applying netural principles rather than choosing metrics that get the results one wants is VERY HARD. I do not profess to be an expert in jurisprudential interpretative theory; I simply know enough about it to know that the things you are saying are the words of a person who knows the Republican talking points on the issue but has not a clue about the actual academic scholarship on originalism, let alone the serious problems in interpreting legal texts that originalism does not always help to solve. Trust me, Bart, you are way out of your league here. I know it is fashionable among conservatives to think of academics as mindless left-wing ideologues, but in fact to be a top flight published legal academic requires a sharp and precise mind, and the people who debate originalism in the academy have forgotten more about these issues than you and I combined are ever going to know. You really should quit while you are behind, Bart. Or better yet, stop making a fool of yourself, subject your ideas to more rigorous scrutiny and research, test your hypotheses, and see if you can get a jurisprudential paper into a major law school's law review. You will find that you need to go a little deeper than facile explanations about Scalia's alleged principles and theories of originalism as mandating a Constitution of unchanged meaning.
Dilan:
If I may paraphrase a great legal thinker, originalism isn't a brooding omnipresence in the sky. It is a category that includes various interpretative metrics. Indeed, some of the interpretative metrics included in originalism definitely do not believe that the meaning of the Constitution is fixed at the origin of the document. Not even Scalia, for instance, believes that. (See his majority opinion on thermal imaging.) Nor does Bork. (See his discussion of libel law in "The Tempting of America" and his wiretapping decision on the DC Circuit.) The Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy (the Federalist Society legal mag) published one issue on "originalism" by various people; I recommended that "Bart" read it a long time ago. As the various authors in that issue pointed out, there's "original meaning", "original intent", "intent of the original founders/authors/ratifiers/judges/experts if they were presented with the current controversy", "understanding of the 'founders'", "understanding of the ratifiers", "understanding of the people", etc.. Then there's levels of "understanding" and "interpretation"; do we want to honour the specifics at the expense of the whole, or are the principles meant (or intended) to inform the specifics? So many combinations to pick from.... It is a disservice to legal scholarship to pretend that the answers are straight-forward; matter of fact, those that make their profession at law should be thankful; were it straight-forward, and were the laws "obvious", there would be no need for lawyers, judges, and law profs, and a JavaBean macro would do all our adjudication. Cheers,
I offered the common definition of originalism as the theory that the meaning of provisions of the Constitution is knowable and fixed at the origin of the document.
On a perhaps related (or unrelated, depending on how you look at the 'science' of jurisprudence) topic, one of the more compelling and curious proofs of the 20th century in mathematics was Kurt Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem: It states (roughly) that for any sufficiently powerful formal system of logic, there are statements that can be made that are true within that system but which cannot be proven to be true within that system. Translated roughly from "Bart"'s language, assuming that a legal system is akin to some formal logic system, there may be things that are "fixed" (that is, that are true), but which just aren't knowable (they either can't be found, or they can't be shown to be true) without recourse to external entities. So much for "Bart"'s 'idealism'.... But law is not math ... alas. Cheers,
dilan said...
BD: I offered the common definition of originalism as the theory that the meaning of provisions of the Constitution is knowable and fixed at the origin of the document. Bart, is that the common definition as put forth by Robert Bork? The common definition as put forth by Antonin Scalia? The common definition as put forth by Akhil Reed Amar? The common definition as put forth by Hugo Black? By critics like John Hart Ely or Paul Brest? Randy Barnett? Could you summarize what the differences are between those various authors' conceptions of originalism? Yes, I provided the basic principle which unites those who practice originalism. Practitioners employ differing means to get to that end - textualism, original understanding and original intent to name three. However, the sought after end of a knowable meaning fixed at the time of the origin of the Constitution is generally the same among Originalists. This is not even a close question. Consult any legal or general dictionary or encyclopedia you choose and you will find a variation of the general end of originalism which I posted. What you are offering, Bart, is a radio talk show definition of originalism, used by right-wing hacks to claim that liberal theories of jurisprudence are unprincipled when compared to conservative theories of jurisprudence. Unless one assumes that the Constitution is a conservative document and fidelity to the Constitution is conservatism, I do not see how one can contend that originalism is either conservative or liberal. Real interpretation is HARD, and applying netural principles rather than choosing metrics that get the results one wants is VERY HARD. No one said that Originalism was easy. Living constitutionalism is far easier because it is not based on neutral principles. Indeed, I suspect that the ease of living constitutionalism just as much as ideology is why judges use it.
one of the more compelling and curious proofs of the 20th century in mathematics was Kurt Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem: It states (roughly) that for any sufficiently powerful formal system of logic, there are statements that can be made that are true within that system but which cannot be proven to be true within that system.
Actually, you can prove such statements true, but only at the cost of contradictions in the formal system. The system can be complete -- that is, all true statements can be proved -- or it can be consistent -- no logical contradictions -- but it can't be both. Of course, calling conservative theories of originalism "formal systems" is far too complimentary. They're muddled thinking, useful for talk radio but not much else.
Consult any legal or general dictionary or encyclopedia you choose and you will find a variation of the general end of originalism which I posted.
Why would you assume that a general dictionary or encyclopedia would contain an authoritative definition of a contested jurisprudential theory? I can tell you that much of what we call originalism-- including, notably, what Scalia and Bork advocate-- does not fit into the definition that you gave earlier in this thread. Both Scalia and Bork believe that the meaning of texts can change over time. You should consult the sources I cited for the relevant discussions. Again, just to come back to the broader point, you are arguing judicial philosophy on the most simplistic levels, and purporting to challenge a law professor who is an expert and who can describe even subtle differences in originalist approaches. You can't come to this argument with Rush Limbaugh talking points about one side following the law as written and the other side not. Oh, and one more thing, living constitutionalism can be very hard to do too. You might want to read Breyer's book Active Liberty or Laurence Tribe's constitutional law treatise to get some idea of this.
@ Mark Field:
[Arne]: one of the more compelling and curious proofs of the 20th century in mathematics was Kurt Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem: It states (roughly) that for any sufficiently powerful formal system of logic, there are statements that can be made that are true within that system but which cannot be proven to be true within that system. Actually, you can prove such statements true, but only at the cost of contradictions in the formal system. The system can be complete -- that is, all true statements can be proved -- or it can be consistent -- no logical contradictions -- but it can't be both. Technically, what you say is true: There is a choice between a system that has unprovable but true statements and an inconsistent system. But in practise, this is not a real choice, as any inconsistent system is essentially useless; once you have any inconsistent statements (which are both true) within the system, it's then pretty trivial to prove any statement you desire as true (although perhaps that feature might come in handy in a formal legal system....) Of course, calling conservative theories of originalism "formal systems" is far too complimentary. They're muddled thinking, useful for talk radio but not much else. But "Bart" is pretending that they are so (as have others as well, for their own rhetorical purposes). It's a winning argument to say: "There is a true answer that can be divined ... and I, of course, have divined it, so I can't be wrong ... or even gainsaid. End of argument." Cheers,
Technically, what you say is true: There is a choice between a system that has unprovable but true statements and an inconsistent system. But in practise, this is not a real choice, as any inconsistent system is essentially useless; once you have any inconsistent statements (which are both true) within the system, it's then pretty trivial to prove any statement you desire as true (although perhaps that feature might come in handy in a formal legal system....)
And my overly elliptical point was that this pretty much describes conservative forms of originalism.
Mark Field:
[Arne]: ... once you have any inconsistent statements (which are both true) within the system ... And my overly elliptical point was that this pretty much describes conservative forms of originalism. I don't think it was overly elliptical; that approach seems to describe current foreign policy, at the very least: "Violence is up, we're winning; violence is down, we're winning...." Cheers,
The late Justice William J. Brennan Jnr characterised "Originalism" thus:
“In its most doctrinaire incarnation, this view demands that Justices discern exactly what the Framers thought about the question under consideration and simply follow that intention in resolving the case before them. It is a view that feigns self-effacing deference to the specific judgments of those who forged our original social compact. But in truth it is little more than arrogance cloaked as humility. It is arrogant to pretend that from our vantage point we can gauge accurately the intent of the Framers on application of principle to specific, contemporary questions. All too often, sources of potential enlightenment such as records of the ratification debates provide sparse or ambiguous evidence of the original intention. Typically, all that can be gleaned is that the Framers themselves did not agree about the application or meaning of particular constitutional provisions, and hid their differences in cloaks of generality. Indeed, it is far from clear whose intention is relevant—that of the drafters, the congressional disputants, or the ratifiers in the states?—or even whether the idea of original intention is a coherent way of thinking about a jointly drafted document drawing its authority from a general assent of the states. And apart from the problematic nature of the sources, our distance of two centuries cannot but work as a prism refracting all we perceive." Other senior common law judges have been even less flattering to the proponents of "Originalism". In his Sir Anthony Mason Honorary Lecture, presented at the Law School, The University of Melbourne, 9th September 1999, entitled "Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent: A Form of Ancestor Worship", (later published in the Melbourne University Law Review [2000] MULR 1, The Hon Mr Justice Michael Kirby recounted that at a conference in Auckland (New Zealand) on constitutional interpretation, there had been a debate between Scalia J and Binnie J of the Supreme Court of Canada. "It was in the context of defending the Canadian approach to that task", said Mr Justice Kirby "that Binnie J let slip the opinion (which he suggested was held by some Canadian judges) that the approach of their counterparts in the United States could only be explained by appreciating that Americans were engaged in a ritual of ancestor worship". "Originalism" is a heretical method of interpretation contrary to the collon law tradition latched upon by the American extreme right so as to provide cover for the evisceration of the constitutionally guaranteed rights which US citizens ought to enjoy".
thanks so much i like very so much your post
حلي الاوريو الفطر الهندي صور تورتة حلى قهوه طريقة عمل السينابون طريقة عمل بلح الشام بيتزا هت كيكة الزبادي حلا سهل صور كيك عجينة العشر دقائق طريقة عمل الدونات طريقة عمل البان كيك طريقة عمل الكنافة طريقة عمل البسبوسة طريقة عمل الكيك طريقة عمل عجينة البيتزا فوائد القرفه
This was a fantastic article. Really loved reading your we blog post. The information was very informative and helpful...
Cara mengobati kanker dengan herbal, Cara mengobati kanker dengan tradisional, Cara mengobati kanker dengan alami, Cara mengobati kanker dengan cepat, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 3, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 4, Cara mengobati kanker stadium awal, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 2, Cara mengobati kanker stadium akhir, Cara mengobati kanker tanpa ke dokter, Gambar obat kanker yang ampuh, Gambar obat kanker yang ampuh, Obat kanker ampuh dengan singkong, Cara mengobati kanker stadium awal tanpa operasi, Obat kanker manjur dari tumbuhan, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 1 tanpa operasi, Obat kanker ampuh dengan daun sirsak, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 2 tanpa operasi, Obat kanker paling mujarab yang efektif, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 3 tanpa operasi, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 3, Cara mengobati kanker stadium 4 tanpa operasi, Obat kanker paling manjur 2016, Cara mengobati kanker stadium akhir tanpa operasi, Pengobatan kanker mujarab tanpa operasi, Cara pengobatan kanker yang manjur, Pengobatan kanker manjur dan aman, Cara pengobatan kanker yang mujarab, Cara pengobatan kanker tanpa operasi, Cara pengobatan kanker yang ampuh, Obat kanker mujarab tanpa operasi, Obat kanker manjur tanpa operasi, Obat De Nature
obat herbal mengobati kanker serviks stadium 3
obat alami untuk mencegah kanker serviks obat medis untuk kanker serviks wwwobat kanker serviks obat vaksin kanker serviks obat untuk mengatasi kanker serviks Tumbuhan untuk obat kanker serviks Obat untuk menyembuhkan kanker serviks obat untuk penderita kanker serviks obat tradisional untuk kanker serviks obat utk kanker serviks obat untuk kanker serviks obat tradisional utk kanker serviks sirsak obat kanker serviks obat sakit kanker serviks hello world obat untuk kanker rahim stadium 3 obat herbal kanker rahim stadium 4 obat kanker rahim stadium 1 1 Obat kanker rahim stadium 2 Obat penyakit herpes kelamin pria
Obat kanker serviks manujur di youtube
obat kanker serviks manjur facebook obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manjur obat herpes genital manju Obat herpes genital manjur Obat herpes genital manujur di youtube Obat kanker dan herpes di twitter obat herpes genital manjur facebook
obat kanker serviks tradisional jawa
Post a Comment
obat kanker serviks tradisional jawa sumatera Obat kanker serviks tradisional sumatera Obat kanker serviks tradisional kalimantan obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal jawa obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal jawa sumatera obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal sumatera obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku pedalaman obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku pedalaman sumatra Obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku jawa obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal s obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku minang obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku sunda Obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku irian obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku dayak obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku kubu obat tradisional kanker serviks suku obat kanker serviks tradisional herbal suku bugis obat herbal herpes genital dompo obat herbal herpes genital dompo simplex
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |