Balkinization  

Tuesday, August 29, 2006

An Originalist Argument Against Rigid Originalism

Brian Tamanaha

James Madison wrote in Federalist 14:

Is it not the glory of the people of America, that whilst they have paid a decent regard to the opinions of former times and other nations, they have not suffered a blind veneration for antiquity, for custom, or for names, to overrule the suggestions of their own good sense, the knowledge of their own situation, and the lessons of their own experience?

Madison was not presenting a theory of consitutional interpretation in this passage; rather, he was making a more general observation about the entire constitutional design.

On originalist terms, it is fair [and perhaps required] to ask whether a person who wrote these words would have signed up for a theory of interpretation, like Scalia's original meaning theory, if the result of such a theory would be a "veneration for antiquity...[or] names" that would "overrule the suggestions of [our] own good sense, the knowledge of our situation, and the lessons of [our] own experience"? What would Jefferson--who repeated that the world belongs to the living and not the dead--have thought about a theory of interpretation that directs us to search through two century old texts to divine answers to questions they never conceived of or entertained?

Interestingly--and once again demonstrating that originalist theories can operate at various levels of abstraction--this way of framing the issue shifts the question away from an inquiry into Madison's specific theory of how a written Constitution should be interpreted. Instead, it poses the more general question of whether Madison would have endorsed a particular original meaning theory of interpretation if, in practice (given the reality of the extreme difficulty and rarity of amending the constitution), it would commit our constitutional system to a decision-making process that relies upon old and spotty sources to trump our present knowledge and experience.

As Jack points out in his detailed posts on the subject, no one engaged in this discussion denies that the Constitution is binding law. The dispute is over how the language of that binding text should be interpreted. Relying upon the above quote (and other ideas circulating at the time, which can be found in Bailyn, To Begin the World Anew), my sense is that Madison (to invoke a venerated "name") would be on Jack's side, at least on the core proposition that the Constitution is a legal document for our time and should be interpreted as such.

I'm not a constitional theorist or a historian--so I'll duck now and get out of the way.

Comments:

You can find Madison quotes on both sides of this issue. In a letter to Henry Lee, Madison said "I entirely concur in the propriety of resorting to the sense in which the Constitution was accepted and ratified by the nation. In that sense alone it is the legitimate Constitution. And if that be not the guide in expounding it, there can be no security for a consistent and stable, more than for a faithful exercise of its powers. If the meaning of the text be sought in the changeable meaning of the words composing it, it is evident that the shape and attributes of the Government must partake of the changes to which the words and phrases of all living languages are constantly subject." July 25, 1824.

Eight years later, in a letter to Jared Ingersoll, he said:

“It was in conformity with the view here taken of the respect due to deliberate and reiterated precedent, that the Bank of the United States, though on the original question held [by Madison] to be unconstitutional, received [Madison’s] executive signature in the year 1817. The act originally establishing a bank had undergone ample discussions in its passage through the several branches of the government. It had been carried into execution through a period of twenty years, with annual legislative recognition,--in one instance, indeed, with a positive ramification of it into a new state,--and with the entire acquiescence of all the local authorities, as well as of the nation at large; to all of which maybe added, a decreasing prospect of any change in the public opinion adverse to the constitutionality of such an institution. A veto from the executive, under these circumstances, with an admission of the expediency, and almost necessity, of the measure, would have been a defiance of all the obligations derived from a course of precedents amounting to the requisite evidence of the national judgment and intentions.” Madison to Jared Ingersoll, June 25, 1831.
 

Chris, if the process of interpretation were to be considered a collective enterprise -- certainly a defensible view -- could anyone ever be sure that the "collective" was actually applying Madison's test for the "sense" of the Constitution?
 

Chris,

The practical difficulties strike me as much greater. I have no idea how anyone would establish, as a factual matter, how the collective had reasoned in reaching its decision. We have that same problem with respect to Madison's own test, and I wish I could say there's agreement among scholars on that subject, but we both know there isn't.

Leaving that aside, the next issue becomes "who decides?". As things stand now, the SCOTUS does. Under your suggestion, would the Court continue to decide if interpretations adopted collectively (through Congress and the President, I suppose) were adopted in the proper sense? If so, is that any different than our current system?
 

Mark, Thanks for the interesting quotes from Madison.

It is important to maintain a key distinction, which I should have drawn more sharply.

It makes sense--and would be consistent with the Federalist 14 quote--that Madison would think it appropriate to be bound by original meaning (and original expectations) during his lifetime. Broadly speaking, this would continue to be drawing from and applying the knowledge and experience of their own (founding) generation.

The question I posed is whether Madison would have thought that this same interpretive strategy would make sense 200 years later. The statement I quote suggests otherwise. Your quotes, which relate to his views in connection with current isssues, do not answer this question (though his awareness of the natural changes of meaning over time is suggestive).

Again, this example of two very different (and equally justifiable) ways of framing the original meaning inquiry demonstates its problematic character.
 

"Madison was not presenting a theory of consitutional interpretation in this passage; rather, he was making a more general observation about the entire constitutional design."

Precisely: Madison was asserting that the people of today should not be bound by the dead hand of the past in drafting a constitution.

Judges, of course, are not drafting a constitution. They're applying one. Indeed, it's perfectly possible for a judge, by engaging in non-originalist "interpretation", to impose the dead hand of the past on a populace who'd rejected it in drafting the clauses he's charged with interpreting.

Hypothetically, a population might try to make a break with what had been the previous tradition of unlimited government, by adopting a constitution creating a limited government posessing only enumerated powers.

Only to be thwarted by a judiciary which "interprets" those limited grants of power so expansively as to recreate the unlimited government the people had consciously rejected.

Wouldn't that be ironic?
 

Brian,

Thanks for clarifying. I did miss your point the first time around.

I think it's possible, almost, to square Madison's statements with a doctrine of "original meaning" similar to Randy Barnett's. Let me set out the argument first and then the important way in which Madison subverts it.

As you alluded to, Jefferson famously wrote to Madison (Sept. 6, 1789) and argued that the earth belongs to the living, that each generation could act only for itself and never bind succeeding ones. Jefferson being Jefferson, he carried this to its logical conclusion:

"On similar ground it may be proved that no society can make a perpetual constitution, or even a perpetual law. The earth belongs always to the living generation. They may manage it then, and what proceeds from it, as they please, during their usufruct. They are masters too of their own persons, and consequently may govern them as they please. But persons and property make the sum of the objects of government. The constitution and the laws of their predecessors extinguished them, in their natural course, with those whose will gave them being. This could preserve that being till it ceased to be itself, and no longer. Every constitution, then, and every law, naturally expires at the end of 19. years. If it be enforced longer, it is an act of force and not of right."

Madison, however, politely disagreed. In his reply of Feb. 4, 1790, he said,

"However applicable in Theory the doctrine may be to a Constitution, it seems liable in practice to some very powerful objections. Would not a Government so often revised become too mutable to retain those prejudices in its favor which antiquity inspires, and which are perhaps a salutary aid to the most rational Government in the most enlightened age? Would not such a periodical revision engender pernicious factions that might not otherwise come into existence? Would not, in fine, a Government depending for its existence beyond a fixed date, on some positive and authentic intervention of the Society itself, be too subject to the casualty and consequences of an actual interregnum?
***
I find no relief from these consequences, but in the received doctrine that a tacit assent may be given to established Constitutions and laws, and that this assent may be inferred, where no positive dissent appears. It seems less impracticable to remedy, by wise plans of Government, the dangerous operation of this doctrine, than to find a remedy for the difficulties inseparable from the other."

I think this response would be consistent with interpretation according to original meaning (or "sense", to use Madison's term).

I think his letter to Ingersoll, which I quoted above, can also be made consistent with this doctrine, subject to the exception I'll mention below. One way to view Madison's attitude about the Bank is to treat him as saying, "I personally thought that the Bank was unconstitutional. However, the actions of my fellow citizens over a long period of time have demonstrated that I was wrong about that. As a good democrat, I acceded to the majority view."

This is at least plausible, because there wouldn't be much doubt that Americans generally were applying the original meaning over that time frame -- it was so close in time to the ratification that no other meaning was possible.

But. Madison didn't stop with the theoretical justification for his about-face on the Bank. He also gave a practical reason (from the letter to Ingersoll): "with an admission of the expediency, and almost necessity, of the measure".

This was a policy reason. Policy reasons are NOT originalist (except in Prof. Balkin's application sense). Nor was this the only policy which Madison supported despite concerns about constitutionality. Examples include the Louisiana Purchase and judicial review.

I don't think there is an easy answer with Madison. My own view is that Madison was much more a pragmatist than a doctrinaire theorist, and a good democrat with real confidence in the people (as your quote from Federalist 14 shows). I think he'd happily aquiesce in text-and-principle. I doubt he'd ever agree to fix the applications of his Constitution to the conditions of 1789.
 

Chris,

Given what I said above, I think you and I agree. If not, let me know.

Brett,

Hypothetically, a population might try to make a break with what had been the previous tradition of unlimited government, by adopting a constitution creating a limited government posessing only enumerated powers.

Only to be thwarted by a judiciary which "interprets" those limited grants of power so expansively as to recreate the unlimited government the people had consciously rejected.


This could only happen, of course, if the people themselves actually acted on the powers given them by the judiciary. Self-restraint is a trump card, and not playing it suggests the judges may have been right.
 

That attitude, Mark, stands in opposition to the whole concept of constitutional rights as protections against the passions of the mob, and of the amending process as a way of making sure fundamental rules only change in explicit ways, due to sustained consensus.

In other words, it stands in opposition to the spirit that motivates constitutions. Of course, it's not an original observation that the idea of constitutions is in fundamental conflict with more direct forms of democracy.
 

That attitude, Mark, stands in opposition to the whole concept of constitutional rights as protections against the passions of the mob, and of the amending process as a way of making sure fundamental rules only change in explicit ways, due to sustained consensus.

I agree, up to a point. I'd make two important distinctions.

First, many of the powers upheld by the Marshall court were powers of the Federal government vis a vis the states. I don't see those as involving fundamental rights, but as a question of which agent the people want to handle certain issues. As to such issues, I don't see much need for the courts to serve a counter-majoritarian function.

Second, the closer you get to the ratification, the more likely it is that the people who accepted and ratified it were simply expressing their own fundamental understanding of how the system was supposed to work. There may still need to be safeguards -- your point about constitutions and democracy is true -- but not necessarily on every issue. Some issues, as Madison showed with the bank, may just need to be settled by practice.
 

Chris,

I say that textually-expressed sense fixes a particular function from possible worlds to constitutional outcomes--maybe that gives us the "boundedness," "containment," and "coherence" part. But it's up to the interpreter to figure out the facts of the world--i.e., to figure out which possible world to plug into that function, yielding the consitutional outcome itself. So maybe that gives us "free, unhampered access to the world" of the sort we want.

I interpret Madison's policy argument for the bank as consistent with what you say here. For that matter, the passage Brian quoted from Federalist 14 suggests that Madison recognized and applauded the "glory" of Americans in determining what world they chose.

If you agree, doesn't that make Madison's view pretty close to yours?
 

You may also want to check out this quotation by Jefferson in his letter to Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1810:

"[L]aws and institutions must go hand in hand with the progress of the human mind. As that becomes more developed, more enlightened, as new discoveries are made, new truths disclosed, and manners and opinions change with the change of circumstances, institutions must advance also, and keep pace with the times. We might as well require a man to wear still the same coat which fitted him when a boy, as civilized society to remain ever under the regimen of their barbarous ancestors."

http://www.monticello.org/reports/quotes/memorial.html
 

Jefferson is pretty much the ultimate NON-originalist in the passages Jonathan and I quoted. In contrast, he was very much a strict constructionist on many other occasions. Here, for example, are portions from his Opinion on the Constitutionality of the Bank:

"I consider the foundation of the Constitution as laid on this ground: That “all powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States or to the people.” [XIIth (sic -- 10th) amendment.] To take a single step beyond the boundaries thus specially drawn around the powers of Congress, is to take possession of a boundless field of power, no longer susceptible of any definition.

****

It is an established rule of construction where a phrase will bear either of two meanings, to give it that which will allow some meaning to the other parts of the instrument, and not that which would render all the others useless. Certainly no such universal power was meant to be given them. It was intended to lace them up straitly within the
enumerated powers, and those without which, as means, these powers could not be carried into effect. It is known that the very power now proposed as a means was rejected as an end by the Convention which formed the Constitution."
 

"Jefferson is pretty much the ultimate NON-originalist in the passages Jonathan and I quoted."

No, actually he isn't. Remember, it's not the position of originalists that the Constitution should never be changed. It's that it should be changed by formal amendment.

This isn't an argument about whether the Constitution should change, it's about whether Article V should be used or circumvented.
 

Remember, it's not the position of originalists that the Constitution should never be changed. It's that it should be changed by formal amendment.

This isn't an argument about whether the Constitution should change, it's about whether Article V should be used or circumvented.


I understand. However, Jefferson's letter to Madison, which I quoted in part, specifically denies that a constitution can last longer than 19 years:

"Every constitution, then, and every law, naturally expires at the end of 19. years. If it be enforced longer, it is an act of force and not of right."
 

I'll grant you that the kind of implicit sunset clause view you're describing is "non-originalist" in the sense that it's different from originalism.

But it's also non-non-originalist, in the sense that non-originalists today are not claiming that the Constitution has expired, and can thus be ignored. They're claiming that it's still binding, but binds us to something nobody ever agreed to.

That's not Jefferson's each generation getting to make it's own decisions. That's a bait and switch.
 

I suspect Jefferson was getting at something more like frequent amendment, or periodic constitutional conventions. Which, while still giving us a changing constitution, would be more in the spirit of Article V, than this "the words remain the same, but now it means something different" business.

My concern here is that the judiciary's Constitution has bee performing what amounts to a drunkard's walk away from the text. At what point does the judiciary's constitution get so far from the text, that the fact that the text was ratified no longer serves as any source of legitimacy for the judiciary's version?

The American people have a great amount of respect for the Constitution the courts claim to be ruling on the basis of. But what supplies the courts with legitimacy when they're close to the text, could strip them of it when they depart too far.

This is a threat I've never seen much indication non-originalists appreciate.
 

But it's also non-non-originalist, in the sense that non-originalists today are not claiming that the Constitution has expired, and can thus be ignored.

Agreed.

I suspect Jefferson was getting at something more like frequent amendment, or periodic constitutional conventions.

That's possible. It's also possible he had in mind some form of radical democracy. It's hard to know because Jefferson wasn't systematic and at various times made statements which appear to be inconsistent.

At what point does the judiciary's constitution get so far from the text, that the fact that the text was ratified no longer serves as any source of legitimacy for the judiciary's version?
***
This is a threat I've never seen much indication non-originalists appreciate.


I think non-originalists do address this and have several responses. I think everybody starts with the text. The problem only arises when people disagree on the meaning to give to that text.

As for the ratification issue, I subscribe to Madison's "tacit assent" principle. In my view, each generation tacitly agrees to the Constitutional text as then understood, including its historical development to that time.

Others, I'm sure, would give different answers. Prof. Balkin, as I understand him, agrees to accept the original ratification, but treats the text as stating very broad principles. The application of those principles can vary over time.

I'm sure there are other answers too. But I don't think it's fair to say that non-originalists "don't appreciate" the issue; they do, even if you may disagree with their solutions.
 

If we really give tacit assent to the "historical development" in the meaning of words, then Madison would be wrong in condemning to Lee the hypothetical situation in which that "the shape and attributes of the Government must partake of the changes to which the words and phrases of all living languages are constantly subject." I don't think we give tacit consent to any such thing.

I'm not sure Madison was right in his letter to Lee, but that wasn't really what I meant by "historical development". By that I meant changes in the consensus understanding of meaning/application, as opposed to word definitions. For example, people now understand Brown to be good law, regardless what might have been the original understanding of the meaning/application of the 14A.

I think that most citizens apply a very pragmatic test to their loyalty. They grow up with, and accept, the society in which they live. They agree, tacitly, to follow the existing rules of that system, rather than rules which may have applied at some time in the past.
 

I don't think that there's tacit consent to contemporary understandings of constitutional application, either, though. If there were, we'd never have ground to reverse settled understandings about constitutional application (e.g., as Brown itself did).

Again in my view, "the current system" includes the possibility of change. I didn't mean that meaning becomes frozen in time, but that people accept current meaning including the prospect of change within accepted rules.

Even if you're right for mere citizens, though, I think that officials who swear the Article VI oath have a duty to abide by the Constitution's own self-conception, which assigns to words like "now," and by extension its other language, the sense they had at the time of the framing.

I realized this distinction after your post above. I'm not sure that your argument is inconsistent with my version of "tacit assent". An oath-taker could, for example, understand the words "this Constitution" to mean "this Constitution as I understand what it means and how it functions today". Indefinite pronouns inevitably create such issues. To paraphrase Heraclitus, can two people ever point to "this" river and mean "the same" one?

That said, your point does have some force and I'm still thinking about it.

FWIW, my article has a big section on Brown. I think the original sense of the P&I clause, applied to the actual facts now, forbids segregation, but that's not something we can just take as a given.

That sounds very interesting, and I'd like to read it, but for some reason SSRN is not letting me download it.
 

Ok, Chris, I've thought about your point (at least for 24 hours). In addition to my previous point, I'd add the following in support of my theory of tacit assent:

1. The oath of office requires the President to "preserve, protect and defend the Constitution of the United States". Use of the more general "the" rather than the somewhat more specific "this" works in my favor.

2. Important features of our system have no textual support at all, but have been derived from structural or philosophical considerations. Examples include sovereignty of the people; the principle of majority/plurality rule; the right to vote for President; judicial review; the President's right to fire officers approved by the Senate; etc. Tacit assent theory incorporates these.

3. My tacit assent theory incorporates current applications as well as meaning.* I think that serves a valuable conservative/preservative function.

*To repeat, I don't mean that tacit assent freezes current applications in place. The accepted process for change is one of the features to which people assent.
 

But Article VI says "this" Constitution, and says that that is what will be the supreme law of the land, suggesting that it was the thing ratified by the conventions

Agreed. My tacit assent theory, because it incorporates historical developments since the founding, does not privilege the original ratification. In a sort of Jeffersonian sense, each generation ratifies for itself.

So I don't think the change suggests that the historicaly-embedded text itself is not supreme; in fact, when the President speaks those words, he is using a different sort of demonstrative expression, precisely because it is not the context in which the President utters those words that matters for setting what the Constitution is. As I see it, that time is the time the Constitution is adopted.

I'm not quite sure what you mean by "historically embedded text". If you mean the Constitution as it has historically developed through today, then I agree. If not -- if you're referring to the original meaning -- then I disagree in the sense that I interpret what the President is promising to do in this sense: he's promising to preserve, protect, and defend the Constitution as he understands what it means today. I'm speculating, of course, but I believe that's what Presidents actually think and what we listeners actually understand and expect.

The historic, textually-expressed sense of the constitutional language is the only thing that gets to count as the Article VI supreme law of the land. As a matter of political morality, sure, we may have consented tacitly to lots of other stuff too--they may be part of "our system" (a better example might be political parties)--but I'm mainly concerned about how to interpret the Constitution itself.

I'm not sure I agree with this, though the issue is moot if you interpret the actual text broadly enough to incorporate some of my examples. Just to pick one, I think that the principle of majority rule is fundamental even if the Constitution itself never uses those words. If you can derive that principle from the text, then we'd agree on the destination and just have some slightly different stories to tell of the journey.
 

I'm not quite sure what you mean by "majority rule." I don't think, as a matter of political morality, that a majority has a right to do just anything it wants to the minority, and I don't think any serious element of our political tradition would say so either.

Agreed. In Jefferson's words, "All, too, will bear in mind this sacred principle, that though the will of the majority is in all cases to prevail, that will to be rightful must be reasonable; that the minority possess their equal rights, which equal law must protect, and to violate would be oppression."

Our system limits majority rule in many ways, but we do expect it to prevail in most cases. For example, nobody believes that when the 17A calls for the election of Senators, it means that the outcome will be decided by a minority of voters. All of those nuances go into the affirmation which people tacitly give to our system even if they have no textual source in the Constitution.
 

Death ends a life, not a relationship.
Agen Judi Online Terpercaya
 

Post a Comment

Older Posts
Newer Posts
Home