Balkinization   |
Balkinization
Balkinization Symposiums: A Continuing List                                                                E-mail: Jack Balkin: jackbalkin at yahoo.com Bruce Ackerman bruce.ackerman at yale.edu Ian Ayres ian.ayres at yale.edu Corey Brettschneider corey_brettschneider at brown.edu Mary Dudziak mary.l.dudziak at emory.edu Joey Fishkin joey.fishkin at gmail.com Heather Gerken heather.gerken at yale.edu Abbe Gluck abbe.gluck at yale.edu Mark Graber mgraber at law.umaryland.edu Stephen Griffin sgriffin at tulane.edu Jonathan Hafetz jonathan.hafetz at shu.edu Jeremy Kessler jkessler at law.columbia.edu Andrew Koppelman akoppelman at law.northwestern.edu Marty Lederman msl46 at law.georgetown.edu Sanford Levinson slevinson at law.utexas.edu David Luban david.luban at gmail.com Gerard Magliocca gmaglioc at iupui.edu Jason Mazzone mazzonej at illinois.edu Linda McClain lmcclain at bu.edu John Mikhail mikhail at law.georgetown.edu Frank Pasquale pasquale.frank at gmail.com Nate Persily npersily at gmail.com Michael Stokes Paulsen michaelstokespaulsen at gmail.com Deborah Pearlstein dpearlst at yu.edu Rick Pildes rick.pildes at nyu.edu David Pozen dpozen at law.columbia.edu Richard Primus raprimus at umich.edu K. Sabeel Rahmansabeel.rahman at brooklaw.edu Alice Ristroph alice.ristroph at shu.edu Neil Siegel siegel at law.duke.edu David Super david.super at law.georgetown.edu Brian Tamanaha btamanaha at wulaw.wustl.edu Nelson Tebbe nelson.tebbe at brooklaw.edu Mark Tushnet mtushnet at law.harvard.edu Adam Winkler winkler at ucla.edu Compendium of posts on Hobby Lobby and related cases The Anti-Torture Memos: Balkinization Posts on Torture, Interrogation, Detention, War Powers, and OLC The Anti-Torture Memos (arranged by topic) Recent Posts The Problem Isn't Signing Statements [UPDATED]
|
Sunday, July 30, 2006
The Problem Isn't Signing Statements [UPDATED]
Marty Lederman
Nor is it the President's assertion of a power to decline to enforce statutes that he thinks are unconstitutional.
Comments:
I find the position set forth in the ABA report more convincing then the position advanced by Mr. Dellinger. With all due respect to Mr. Dellinger, most of his argument strikes me as a red herring. The current issue concerns signing statements. We are discussing the authority of the President when he must choose to either sign or veto a bill. We are not currently confronted with the problem of a President who has to decide whether to enforce a bill that was enacted under a prior administration or was enacted by overriding his veto. Those are difference circumstances that must be analyzed differently. We are instead confronted with the problem of whether the President has the right to sign a bill and then pick and choose which provisions of it he will enforce.
Mr. Dellinger writes that “the Constitution does not force the president to choose between two starkly unpalatable options: veto the entire bill or enforce an unconstitutional provision.” Again, with all due respect to Mr. Dellinger, that is exactly the stark choice that the Presentment Clause gives to the President. He must either approve all parts of the bill or reject it in toto. That is how George Washington understood the Presentment Clause, and it is how the United States Supreme Court interpreted it in Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417 (1998), when it held that the line-item veto violates the Presentment Clause. Note that Mr. Dellinger’s argument for allowing Presidents to declare laws unconstitutional in signing statements is precisely the same argument that was made for the wisdom of the line item veto. If Congress cannot create a narrowly tailored line item veto for the President, then surely the President cannot create an unbridled line item veto for himself. I find Mr. Dellinger’s argument that the Oval Office should instead police itself even less persuasive. Maybe Plato is correct that the benevolent dictator is the best form of government, but surely history has taught us that not all dictators are benevolent. I don’t want to trust that the President will be benevolent in the exercise his power. I want the Constitutional scheme of checks and balances upheld, even at the price of a less efficient administration. I consider my freedom worth that cost.
The principle of judicial supremacy to interpret the Constitution is among the most settled of U.S. precedents. Yes, the political branches can excercise their own interpretations, but the courts have the final say.
I'd take this a step further and say that the courts, at least within limits, should have the final say, that it's essential for a democratic system.
For what it is worth, the fact that almost all judges endorse judicial supremacy does not count as dispositive evidence for "constitutional protestants" anymore than does the fact that all members of the Roman Catholic hierarchy endorse papal supremacy (or at least the supremacy of the teaching magisterium as defined by the Vaticum and the Congregation for the Defense of the Faith) proves relevant for religious protestants. There may be good arguments for judicial supremacy--see, for example, the articles by Fred Schauer and Larry Alexander (which, I confess, do not persuade me)--but the fact that judges have a particular view of their own authority isn't one of them.
Incidentally, the notion that a President can always appeal to a court for some "definitive answer" as to constitutionality assumes that standing is always available. Even the present Court has scarcely taken the position that it has unlimited authority to hear any and all interesting conundrums about constitutional law. There are, of course, courts that have more expansive notions of standing, including the Israel High Court and the Indian Supreme Court.
While I think the attitude of the Justices is an important factor, I think it has less weight than the structural role the Court plays -- IMO, that requires judicial supremacy. That said, I'm not sure the analogy to Catholics and Protestants undermines JaO's argument. In the case of the SCOTUS, it is, to paraphrase a quote, supreme because it is final. The Catholic Church, in contrast, lacks the monopoly on religion which the Court exercises under US law. I think that the existence of that monopoly requires that we give more weight to the actual attitude of the Justices than Protestants give to the Pope.
I'm not sure what it means to say that the Court exercises "a monopoly" with regard to the interpretation of the Constitution. On occasion it has said this, but to some extent it is like whistling past the graveyard insofar, for better and for worse, it is often the case that other political actors, especially, ironically enough, relatively low-visibility bureaucrats or relatively poltically independent sheriffs and the like, scarcely have brought their behavior ito line with that presumptively desired by the Court. Indeed, as has been argued in earlier postings relating to John Yoo and the pratice of law more generally, actors who desire to maintain their own agendss instead of signing on to the Court's, can easily find lawyers to create distinctions that can stifle any easy notion of "compliance."
One can argue such issues either on empirical grounds--to what extent does the Supreme Court actually shape behavior with regard to anything particularly important where there is significant social cleavage--or normatively--to what extent ought we assign papalist (not "papist," incidentally, which I have been persuaded is a derogatory term) authority to the Court or, on the contrary, adopt a far more protestant (or "rabbinic") view of multiple interpreters. I am indeed one of the latter theorists, but, as suggested, I base my theory on a substantial empirical foundation of the actual practice of American constitutional politics. And that includes some role for independent presidential interpretation. If we really reject such a notion, then I suggest, for starters, that we tear down the Lincoln Memorial (though, of course, the Memorial doesn't highlight Lincoln's disdain an ddisregard to Taney's opinion in Ex parte Merryman).
I should let JaO defend this point, since it's really his (?)....
I'm not sure what it means to say that the Court exercises "a monopoly" with regard to the interpretation of the Constitution. On occasion it has said this, but to some extent it is like whistling past the graveyard insofar, for better and for worse, it is often the case that other political actors, especially, ironically enough, relatively low-visibility bureaucrats or relatively poltically independent sheriffs and the like, scarcely have brought their behavior ito line with that presumptively desired by the Court. Even within the Catholic Church -- where the papacy does have recognized, ultimate authority -- individual parishoners, priests, and even bishops can act contrary to official doctrine. They can't do it for long, though; only as long as the Church chooses to allow the behavior to persist. The Church may pronounce its doctrines in general terms, but it must enforce them in individual cases. Something very similar happens in the US. There's a good deal of room for resistance to decisions; the segregation experience tells us that even if nothing else does. Each act of resistance must then be challenged, just as it is in the Church. The key difference I see, and the one that caused me to intrude, was this: the Catholic Church has jurisdiction only over Catholics. It can't enforce its doctrine over those who worship outside of it. In contrast, the SCOTUS has constitutional authority over "all cases in law and equity, arising under this Constitution". As long as US citizens recognize the Constitution as authority, the Court gets a monopoly on deciding cases and thus a monopoly on doctrine. There's no doubt that to a great extent this difference is pragmatic. The Catholic Church claims universal jurisdiction; that's what "catholic" means. But the Church lacks an agreed basis for that claim, whereas the Constitution provides that basis for the Court. It still does happen that Presidents, for example, challenge the Court: "Mr. Marshall has made his decision, now let him enforce it." But when they do, there is (IMO) general agreement that they've trespassed on the Court's Constitutional authority. Thus, I think that JaO's point has some force and that the analogy to the Church doesn't undermine that point. Having said all this, I want to make clear that (1) I consider JaO's point much less important than the structural considerations which (IMO) require the Court to exercise judicial supremacy in certain (not all) cases; (2) I completely agree that "multiple interpreters" have, as a matter of historical fact, contributed to Constitution interpretation, and further agree that they should do so in many cases.
See my comment at tpmcafe, persuasively refuting, on a point-by-point basis, all the arguments the former OLC lawyers make about signing statements, here: http://www.tpmcafe.com/blog/specialguests/2006/jul/31/untangling_the_debate_on_signing_statements#comment-149480
See my comment at tpmcafe, persuasively refuting, on a point-by-point basis, all the arguments the former OLC lawyers make about signing statements
I'm not persuaded by several of your arguments. In no particular order: 1. Use of the veto. I don't see this as solving the problem. Suppose the President does veto a bill but Congress passes it over the veto. Under your theory, must the President then enforce it anyway, or can he take it to the courts? If the latter, then I don't see why the veto is necessary at all; surely the President is not estopped to challenge a statute in court just because he signed it. That would serve no purpose except to inhibit judicial review, which is what you contend should be the proper recourse anyway (and I agree with that). Nor will negotiation suffice. If Congress disagrees, there is an impasse. The only way to resolve such a dispute is to pass the bill and let the Court decide. 2. Jefferson. Yes, you can interpret his refusal to continue prosecution under the Sedition Act as an exercise in prosecutorial discretion, but that's hard to do when he made so many comments giving as his reason for that decision his firm belief that the Act was unconstitutional. Besides, calling it "prosecutorial discretion" doesn't help much when the prosecutors are part of the executive. It's just another facet of the same behavior. 3. Faithful execution. It's true that ONE way to execute the Constitution faithfully is to enforce an unconstitutional statute. Another, though, is to refuse to enforce it. This really gets back to No. 1. 4. Most laws are not unconstitutional on their face, but only as applied. I can't see any harm in the President signing a law which might be abused, but which if not abused is a good law. The real problem with Bush is his manifest bad faith in exercising Presidential powers. It's not just signing statements or refusal to enforce, it's ALL of it. I'm not sure I'd change established practice just because of him (I might if it were repeated by future Presidents). I agree that (a) the preferred method of determining unconstitutionality is judicial review; (b) signing statements should NOT be treated as part of the legislative history; and (c) refusal to enforce cases should be both rare and part of an effort to obtain judicial review. That still leaves some room for both the statements and the refusal to enforce.
mark:
There's no need for refusal to enforce. First, the President does have the veto. The veto may leave a few situations where the President is faced with the question of what to do with a statute passed over the veto or with a law signed by a predecessor. Still, in most situations, the veto is there. The question is why should the President have ANY power-- especially since line-item vetos are clearly unconstitutional under controlling precedent-- to refuse to enforce, for ANY reason, a statute that he could have vetoed? The only actual answer seems to be that Presidents don't want to take the political hit of a veto, but that's a political hit the framers expected them to take. Second, in the narrow circumstances you posit, the President still has the courts. He can appoint competent counsel to defend the law and seek to challenge it. But he has to abide by it unless and until the judiciary adopts his position. That's how you faithfully execute the laws. (If the issue is an application of an otherwise constitutional law, the President should do this if and when the issue comes up. No signing statement is required.) Finally, if the President really does not feel he can follow the law, he can resign. Those options cover all the possible situations. There is no reason for a signing statement.
Dilan, your post repeats your original argument, but doesn't address any of the counterpoints.
I'm sympathetic to your view. However, the former OLC attorneys do make several good points which you haven't addressed: 1. Enforcing an unconstitutional law, even if the President signed it, is inconsistent with the oath to "preserve, protect and defend the Constitution". It's also inconsistent with the obligation to faithfully enforce the laws, assuming we all agree that the phrase "the laws" includes the Constitution. 2. Most laws are not unconstitutional on their face, but can be unconstitutional as applied in certain cases. Surely the President is not obligated to veto a law which might conceivably be abused; that would require vetoing almost every law. 3. There is support in the historical record for the practice. 4. Circumstances might change. I'll give you an example: was Lincoln, in the middle of the Civil War, obligated to enforce the Fugitive Slave Law (assuming the law was Constitutional)? Another: Was Jefferson really obligated to continue the Sedition Act prosecutions? Your proposed solution doesn't meet these points.
Mark:
1. Nothing in the Constitution says that the President gets to say what the Constitution means. Rather, the "Judicial Power" of the United States goes to the courts. Thus, the way the President preserves, protects, and defends the Constitution and takes care that the laws be faithfully executed is by obeying statutes and bringing unconstitutional statutes to the attention of the courts and obeying them in the meantime. 2. I answered the "unconstitutional as applied" point. The President can and should veto the law and ask that the unconstitutional application be remedied. If the President is dealing with a law already signed or passed over his veto, he can wait until an unconstitutional application comes up and then ask the courts to review it. But the line-item veto is unconstitutional under controlling authority, and that includes the line-item veto of a provision that the President thinks is unconstitutional. 3. Have there been signing statements? Yes. But the examples of Presidents dealing with allegedly unconstitutional legislation that the authors gave were unpersuasive. Refusing to prosecute people under a criminal statute is simply not the same thing as saying a law has no force. One is the classic executive power of prosecutorial discretion; the other is flatly disobeying Marbury v. Madison. 4. Again, those issues are prosecutorial discretion issues. The executive branch can refuse to prosecute under criminal statutes, and that's simply very different than purporting to line-item veto a bill. And by the way, the fugitive slave law is a TERRIBLE example. It was perfectly constitutional prior to the enactment of the 13th Amendment, and indeed was specifically authorized under the Constitution. Lincoln, had I said, could refuse to prosecute under it, but he had no power to say that it was unconstitutional; it wasn't.
Nothing in the Constitution says that the President gets to say what the Constitution means.
Nothing in the Constitution says this, either: the way the President preserves, protects, and defends the Constitution and takes care that the laws be faithfully executed is by obeying statutes and bringing unconstitutional statutes to the attention of the courts and obeying them in the meantime. It doesn't seem fair for you to demand text for my point but to rely on inference for yours. In any case, there is text for the OLC view: "he shall take care that the laws be faithfully executed." To me, that means enforcing the Constitution as well. I answered the "unconstitutional as applied" point. The President can and should veto the law and ask that the unconstitutional application be remedied. You did say this; I don't find it persuasive for all cases. Lots of times the unconstitutional application can't even be foreseen. I don't think the President is bound to enforce an unconstitutional application he couldn't have foreseen just because he signed the bill into law. Refusing to prosecute people under a criminal statute is simply not the same thing as saying a law has no force. It seems very similar to me. And by the way, the fugitive slave law is a TERRIBLE example. It was perfectly constitutional prior to the enactment of the 13th Amendment, and indeed was specifically authorized under the Constitution. That's why I used it as an example. Are you seriously asserting that Lincoln was obligated to enforce that law at any time after Fort Sumter?
Mark:
If the take care clause includes the Constitution, then the President violates it by SIGNING unconstitutional legislation. So that argument doesn't get you anywhere. (By the way, if we were to get into the history running up to the Constitution, it is pretty clear that the take care clause related to laws, and that the framers expected that the President would obey Congressional statutes and that was the purpose of the clause. But that's neither here nor there because even if it includes the Constitution, that just makes clear that the President is prohibited from signing unconstitutional legislation, with or without a signing statement.) "That's why I used it as an example. Are you seriously asserting that Lincoln was obligated to enforce that law at any time after Fort Sumter?" Well whether he was or not is measured by a different metric, i.e., the laws of war and insurrection. We are not talking about whether a President, during a time of actual insurrection, may decide to suspend generally applicable laws that relate to the territories that are under rebellion. That's the Lincoln / fugitive slave issue. But my point was, that DOESN'T establish the President's power to declare the law unconstitutional. Indeed, it is perfectly constitutional. There may simply be a power to override it under the Commander-in-Chief power (although it may also be that the proper procedure was to go to Congress).
If the take care clause includes the Constitution, then the President violates it by SIGNING unconstitutional legislation.
Fair point, but I can't see that two wrongs make a right. If he signs it in violation of his oath (assuming, that is, that he recognizes the problem at the time but signs anyway), violating it afterwards hardly seems like the best solution. Well whether he was or not is measured by a different metric, i.e., the laws of war and insurrection. We are not talking about whether a President, during a time of actual insurrection, may decide to suspend generally applicable laws that relate to the territories that are under rebellion. That's the Lincoln / fugitive slave issue. I'm not sure I follow you here. As I understand it, the habeas corpus clause has been interpreted to give only Congress the right of suspending the writ. What other authority do you think the President has to ignore a law of general application? I want to emphasize that I think the range of cases we're discussing is fairly narrow. I'm somewhere between you and the OLC attorneys. I just think there are some limited cases in which refusal to enforce is appropriate.
"I'm not sure I follow you here. As I understand it, the habeas corpus clause has been interpreted to give only Congress the right of suspending the writ. What other authority do you think the President has to ignore a law of general application?"
I am not sure whether the President can suspend generally applicable laws during an insurrection or not. (Note, we are talking about fugitive slave laws, not habeas.) But if he does have that power, it's part of the Commander-in-Chief power and would have nothing to do with whether the statutes are unconstitutional. Indeed, your hypothetical involved a flatly constitutional (at the time) statute.
My example can work two different ways. Both assume that the Fugitive Slave Law was constitutional when passed.
Post a Comment
Hypothetical #1: Assume that the President has war powers. The FSL interferes with the exercise of those powers and Lincoln reasonably believes that the FSL is therefore unconstitutional as applied. Can Lincoln refuse to comply with it on this basis? Hypothetical #2: Assume that the FSL does not interfere with any war power. Is Lincoln obligated therefore to enforce it despite the obvious absurdity of doing so?
|
Books by Balkinization Bloggers Linda C. McClain and Aziza Ahmed, The Routledge Companion to Gender and COVID-19 (Routledge, 2024) David Pozen, The Constitution of the War on Drugs (Oxford University Press, 2024) Jack M. Balkin, Memory and Authority: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation (Yale University Press, 2024) Mark A. Graber, Punish Treason, Reward Loyalty: The Forgotten Goals of Constitutional Reform after the Civil War (University of Kansas Press, 2023) Jack M. Balkin, What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Most Controversial Decision - Revised Edition (NYU Press, 2023) Andrew Koppelman, Burning Down the House: How Libertarian Philosophy Was Corrupted by Delusion and Greed (St. Martin’s Press, 2022) Gerard N. Magliocca, Washington's Heir: The Life of Justice Bushrod Washington (Oxford University Press, 2022) Joseph Fishkin and William E. Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution: Reconstructing the Economic Foundations of American Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2022) Mark Tushnet and Bojan Bugaric, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (Oxford University Press 2021). Mark Philip Bradley and Mary L. Dudziak, eds., Making the Forever War: Marilyn B. Young on the Culture and Politics of American Militarism Culture and Politics in the Cold War and Beyond (University of Massachusetts Press, 2021). Jack M. Balkin, What Obergefell v. Hodges Should Have Said: The Nation's Top Legal Experts Rewrite America's Same-Sex Marriage Decision (Yale University Press, 2020) Frank Pasquale, New Laws of Robotics: Defending Human Expertise in the Age of AI (Belknap Press, 2020) Jack M. Balkin, The Cycles of Constitutional Time (Oxford University Press, 2020) Mark Tushnet, Taking Back the Constitution: Activist Judges and the Next Age of American Law (Yale University Press 2020). Andrew Koppelman, Gay Rights vs. Religious Liberty?: The Unnecessary Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2020) Ezekiel J Emanuel and Abbe R. Gluck, The Trillion Dollar Revolution: How the Affordable Care Act Transformed Politics, Law, and Health Care in America (PublicAffairs, 2020) Linda C. McClain, Who's the Bigot?: Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (Oxford University Press, 2020) Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin, Democracy and Dysfunction (University of Chicago Press, 2019) Sanford Levinson, Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies (Duke University Press 2018) Mark A. Graber, Sanford Levinson, and Mark Tushnet, eds., Constitutional Democracy in Crisis? (Oxford University Press 2018) Gerard Magliocca, The Heart of the Constitution: How the Bill of Rights became the Bill of Rights (Oxford University Press, 2018) Cynthia Levinson and Sanford Levinson, Fault Lines in the Constitution: The Framers, Their Fights, and the Flaws that Affect Us Today (Peachtree Publishers, 2017) Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Realistic Theory of Law (Cambridge University Press 2017) Sanford Levinson, Nullification and Secession in Modern Constitutional Thought (University Press of Kansas 2016) Sanford Levinson, An Argument Open to All: Reading The Federalist in the 21st Century (Yale University Press 2015) Stephen M. Griffin, Broken Trust: Dysfunctional Government and Constitutional Reform (University Press of Kansas, 2015) Frank Pasquale, The Black Box Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information (Harvard University Press, 2015) Bruce Ackerman, We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution (Harvard University Press, 2014) Balkinization Symposium on We the People, Volume 3: The Civil Rights Revolution Joseph Fishkin, Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (Oxford University Press, 2014) Mark A. Graber, A New Introduction to American Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, 2013) John Mikhail, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment (Cambridge University Press, 2013) Gerard N. Magliocca, American Founding Son: John Bingham and the Invention of the Fourteenth Amendment (New York University Press, 2013) Stephen M. Griffin, Long Wars and the Constitution (Harvard University Press, 2013) Andrew Koppelman, The Tough Luck Constitution and the Assault on Health Care Reform (Oxford University Press, 2013) James E. Fleming and Linda C. McClain, Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues (Harvard University Press, 2013) Balkinization Symposium on Ordered Liberty: Rights, Responsibilities, and Virtues Andrew Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Harvard University Press, 2013) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Failing Law Schools (University of Chicago Press, 2012) Sanford Levinson, Framed: America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance (Oxford University Press, 2012) Linda C. McClain and Joanna L. Grossman, Gender Equality: Dimensions of Women's Equal Citizenship (Cambridge University Press, 2012) Mary Dudziak, War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences (Oxford University Press, 2012) Jack M. Balkin, Living Originalism (Harvard University Press, 2011) Jason Mazzone, Copyfraud and Other Abuses of Intellectual Property Law (Stanford University Press, 2011) Richard W. Garnett and Andrew Koppelman, First Amendment Stories, (Foundation Press 2011) Jack M. Balkin, Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in an Unjust World (Harvard University Press, 2011) Gerard Magliocca, The Tragedy of William Jennings Bryan: Constitutional Law and the Politics of Backlash (Yale University Press, 2011) Bernard Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets: Punishment and the Myth of Natural Order (Harvard University Press, 2010) Bruce Ackerman, The Decline and Fall of the American Republic (Harvard University Press, 2010) Balkinization Symposium on The Decline and Fall of the American Republic Ian Ayres. Carrots and Sticks: Unlock the Power of Incentives to Get Things Done (Bantam Books, 2010) Mark Tushnet, Why the Constitution Matters (Yale University Press 2010) Ian Ayres and Barry Nalebuff: Lifecycle Investing: A New, Safe, and Audacious Way to Improve the Performance of Your Retirement Portfolio (Basic Books, 2010) Jack M. Balkin, The Laws of Change: I Ching and the Philosophy of Life (2d Edition, Sybil Creek Press 2009) Brian Z. Tamanaha, Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton University Press 2009) Andrew Koppelman and Tobias Barrington Wolff, A Right to Discriminate?: How the Case of Boy Scouts of America v. James Dale Warped the Law of Free Association (Yale University Press 2009) Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel, The Constitution in 2020 (Oxford University Press 2009) Heather K. Gerken, The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It (Princeton University Press 2009) Mary Dudziak, Exporting American Dreams: Thurgood Marshall's African Journey (Oxford University Press 2008) David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007) Ian Ayres, Super Crunchers: Why Thinking-By-Numbers is the New Way to be Smart (Bantam 2007) Jack M. Balkin, James Grimmelmann, Eddan Katz, Nimrod Kozlovski, Shlomit Wagman and Tal Zarsky, eds., Cybercrime: Digital Cops in a Networked Environment (N.Y.U. Press 2007) Jack M. Balkin and Beth Simone Noveck, The State of Play: Law, Games, and Virtual Worlds (N.Y.U. Press 2006) Andrew Koppelman, Same Sex, Different States: When Same-Sex Marriages Cross State Lines (Yale University Press 2006) Brian Tamanaha, Law as a Means to an End (Cambridge University Press 2006) Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution (Oxford University Press 2006) Mark Graber, Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil (Cambridge University Press 2006) Jack M. Balkin, ed., What Roe v. Wade Should Have Said (N.Y.U. Press 2005) Sanford Levinson, ed., Torture: A Collection (Oxford University Press 2004) Balkin.com homepage Bibliography Conlaw.net Cultural Software Writings Opeds The Information Society Project BrownvBoard.com Useful Links Syllabi and Exams |