For the Balkinization symposium on Robert Post, The Taft Court: Making Law for a Divided Nation, 1921–1930 (Cambridge University Press, 2024).
James E. Fleming
I. Introduction
Congratulations
to Robert Post for completing his monumental The Taft Court. It is a staggering, inspiring, and illuminating
achievement! The careers of a number of prominent law professors have been
weighed down by the heavy burden of expectations arising from the Oliver
Wendell Holmes Devise History of the Supreme Court. Though Robert notes that he
began working on the book 35 years ago (xxv), he has borne that burden well.
The book has a fresh, energetic, and urgent feel to it. Indeed, his completion
of the book at this moment is unexpectedly timely in ways I will sketch.
I recently
published Constructing Basic Liberties: A Defense of
Substantive Due Process, a vigorous defense of substantive due process
at a time when it is imperiled. Therefore, I will focus on Post’s analysis in
Part V of the Taft Court’s protection of fundamental liberties through
substantive due process. This was, after all, during the Lochner era. In these comments, I will be unabashedly and
unapologetically presentist. After all, I am not an historian but a normative
constitutional theorist, and so I will leave it to others to assess whether
Post gets the history right. Instead, I shall focus on the implications of his
analysis of the Taft Court for understanding and criticizing the Roberts Court.
In terms of the subtitle of his book, both courts face the challenges of
“making law for a divided nation.”
II. Three
General Parallels between the Taft and Roberts Courts
I was
struck by three general parallels between the Taft Court and the Roberts Court,
especially since the election of Donald Trump as President in 2016. First, just
as President Warren Harding between 1921 and 1923 had the opportunity to
appoint four justices to the Court—an unusually large number for such a short
period—President Donald Trump got to appoint three justices between 2017 and
2020. In both instances, their appointments of conservative justices produced
notably more conservative Courts.
Second,
Post powerfully illuminates the ways in which World War I contributed to the
building of the modern administrative state with a strong national government.
These developments fueled progressive hopes of continuing to harness the
federal government during peacetime to promote positive benefits for the good of
the people. At the same time, they aroused conservative fears of “socialistic”
government and longing for a “return to normalcy”—basically to “the older
ideals of laissez-faire
individualism” (683) thought to have obtained before World War I.
Although we
have not had a war of the scope of World War I in recent years, we have seen
the continuing expansion of the administrative state and with it the backlash
of conservatives’ never-ending
assault on the administrative state. Similarly, in response to the
extension of constitutional rights and antidiscrimination law to protect
historically subordinate groups—what conservatives have seen as the Warren
Court Revolution—we have lived through the conservatives’ longstanding war on
the “Warren Court.” This is a broad concept that includes many of the
developments actually occurring through later courts and federal and state legislation.
Progressives
have celebrated these developments as great achievements of our constitutional
culture in securing the blessings of liberty and the status of equality for all.
But conservatives have vilified them as illegitimate and sought a return to
normalcy—whether through (1) restoring
the “lost” libertarian Constitution that has been “in exile” since 1937;
(2) overruling liberal precedents in order to return to a pre-Warren Court
status quo; or (3) going back to the purported original meaning of the
Constitution.
(By the
way, conservative “returns to normalcy” seem invariably to be returns to when
conservatives ruled the country, the states of affairs liberals and
progressives have sought to reform. This mindset reached its nadir in Senator Tim
Scott’s recent call for a “return to normalcy” by electing Trump to a second
term. Talk about “defining
normalcy down,” as Charlie Sykes aptly put it in The Bulwark.)
Three, the
Taft Court, like the Roberts Court, had a chief justice who was deeply
conservative yet who occasionally moderated the conservativism of his Court
through majority opinions or dissents rejecting the views of his more radical
conservative colleagues.
To be
clear, Post does not explicitly make these three comparisons—he is writing the
history of the Taft Court, not a criticism of the Roberts Court. Still, he
implicitly tees them up for readers like me to make.
III. Similarities
between the Taft and Roberts Courts’ Conceptions of Fundamental Liberties
I also see
uncanny resemblances between Post’s analysis of the Taft Court’s protection of
liberty in the substantive due process decisions of Meyer v. Nebraska and Pierce
v. Society of Sisters, on the one hand, and the Roberts Court’s protections
of freedom of speech and religious liberty in 303 Creative v. Elenis, on the other. The Nebraska and Oregon
legislatures in Meyer and Pierce, in the wake of World War I,
clearly believed that government should promote American ideals through
prohibiting the teaching of modern languages (including German) and requiring
everyone to attend public schools. The Colorado legislature in 303 Creative, through its
antidiscrimination law’s prohibition of discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation, clearly thought that it was promoting civic ideals of tolerance
and respect for all in securing the status of equal citizenship for LGBTQ
persons, including same-sex couples who planned to marry.
Justice
McReynolds for the majority in Meyer
and Pierce rebuffed civic republican
projects of fostering American ideals and cultivating a common civic culture on
the basis of an antitotalitarian conception of liberty. In Meyer, McReynolds specifically analogized Nebraska’s forbiddance of
teaching German to totalitarian measures that would submerge the individual in
the government’s project of crafting ideal citizens. Similarly, in Pierce, he rejected Oregon’s requirement
of attending public schools as treating children as “mere creatures of the
state” to be “standardized” by the government in forming ideal citizens. The
Taft Court officially grounded these decisions in substantive due process. Yet
in Griswold v. Connecticut, decided
in 1965, Justice Douglas for the majority eschews substantive due process and recasts
Meyer and Pierce as First Amendment cases.
The Roberts
Court, though dubious about substantive due process in general (see Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization),
does not repudiate Meyer and Pierce so much as complete the recasting
of their concerns (together with those of West
Virginia v. Barnette in invalidating a compulsory flag salute in public
schools) into First Amendment commitments protecting against governmental
compulsion of an orthodoxy in 303
Creative. These First Amendment commitments stem from not only freedom of
speech but also religious liberty. In 303
Creative, Justice Gorsuch for the 6-3 conservative majority condemned
Colorado’s antidiscrimination law (in Orwellian terms) as imposing a
governmental orthodoxy upon honorable dissenters. The Court’s invoking of
Orwell and its framing of Colorado’s salutary project of protecting LGBTQ
persons against discrimination as compelling a governmental orthodoxy echo Meyer and Pierce’s warnings against government engaging in totalitarian
standardization of people.
What is
more, as suggested at the outset, just as the Taft Court viewed itself as
restoring the normalcy of a pre-World War I order, the Roberts Court evidently
aspires to restore the normalcy of a status quo that preceded the Warren Court Revolution.
(We see this not only in Dobbs but
also in a number of religious liberty cases.) (1) A status quo that is deeply
rooted in history and tradition (conceived narrowly as concrete historical
practices embodied in the common law and statute books rather than abstract
aspirational principles). (2) One moreover that conceives the Constitution as codifying
pre-existing common law rights instead of establishing abstract rights to be
built out over time on the basis of experience, new insights, and moral
progress. (3) And one that maintains fidelity to the original meaning of the
Constitution (conceived as relatively specific expectations of the framers and
ratifiers rather than abstract commitments embodied in the text to be built out
over time).
The only
criticism I have of Post’s analysis of substantive due process is that he may
make progressive assumptions about economic liberties today that blunt the
similarities between today’s conservatives and the conservatives of the Taft
Court. He rightly observes that the Taft Court conservatives did not
distinguish economic liberty from personal liberty, but viewed both as required
for “the maintenance of personal independence and adult moral agency” (828)—and
therefore Meyer, Pierce, and Adkins v.
Children’s Hospital were of a piece with one another. (Today, by contrast,
many conservatives would protect economic liberties but not personal liberties.)
Post writes,
“[T]he normative aspect of property is almost invisible to modern readers. It
is hard for us now to appreciate just how thoroughly members of the Taft Court
conceptualized property as constitutive of personality, as prerequisite for the
formation of adult independence and agency.” (827) He also says, “In our own
time, in the wake of the constitutional revisions of the New Deal, property has
largely been drained of this moral significance.” (835) Thus, Post seems to
assume that people today do not view economic liberty as essential to
individual moral independence, though personal liberty is. That certainly is
the way many liberals and progressives view the matter. But here I believe he
underestimates the degree to which conservatives today reject that view and
continue to embody the Taft Court understanding that economic liberty is fundamental to and constitutive of
personality and moral independence.
Many
contemporary conservatives, moreover, do not share the liberal and progressive
view that it was a constitutional disaster for courts aggressively to enforce
economic liberty during the Lochner
era. They have rehabilitated Lochner
or resurrected the Lochner era mindset
that Post’s analysis elaborates so vividly. Even though many conservatives
today avoid invoking Lochner by name,
they champion many ideas critical of governmental regulation that are
reminiscent of the Lochner era, e.g.,
through their doctrines concerning federalism, separation of powers, and First
Amendment rather than through substantive due process.
In short,
Post’s analysis of the Taft Court’s approach to social and economic legislation
illuminates what Paul Krugman would call libertarian “zombie”
ideas that continue to stalk the earth, endangering constitutional progress
and use of government to face modern challenges and pursue good things for the
people.
Furthermore,
I believe that Post’s analysis of Adkins
is spot on, and it sheds light on additional similarities between Taft Court
conservatives and Roberts Court conservatives. He primarily views Adkins through the lens of Justice
Sutherland’s moral conception of protecting fundamental liberties rather than
as reflecting hostility to class legislation, which seems exactly right. When I
read Post’s account of Sutherland I immediately thought of Randy
Barnett’s libertarian arguments for a presumption of liberty and against
governmental regulation. I also thought of Justice Thomas’s arguments in New York State Rifle & Pistol
Association v. Bruen for a presumption in favor of gun rights and against
governmental regulation. I am not saying that Post’s account is presentist. I
am saying that today’s conservatives seem more like the Taft Court’s conservatives
than he specifically acknowledges. As I put the matter in my book, Constructing Basic Liberties, today many
conservatives’ worldviews embody “Lochner’s
revenge” on West Coast Hotel (for
overruling Adkins and therewith the Lochner era).
IV. The
Analogies between the Adkins and Dobbs
Finally,
Post’s analysis enables us to see similarities between the Taft Court’s
decision in Adkins and the Roberts
Court’s decision in Dobbs. To be
sure, there are fundamental differences doctrinally—Adkins reinvigorated substantive due process (in particular, Lochner era protection of liberty of
contract), whereas Dobbs takes a
sledgehammer to it. Moreover, Dobbs
purports to have learned the lessons of the errors of the Lochner era—indeed, it tars Roe
v. Wade and Planned Parenthood v. Casey
with the brush of Lochner (even as it
resurrects the Lochner era mindset
through other doctrines).
Still, I want to bring out two similarities between Adkins and Dobbs. One, Post opens his analysis of Adkins by stating that it “was the ‘chef d’oeuvre of the Taft Court,’...the decision that decisively
set the Taft Court on the path toward normalcy.” (755) Dobbs is precisely analogous for the Roberts Court, a defining case
that purports to set the Court on the path toward the pre-Roe “normalcy” of protecting only basic liberties that are deeply
rooted in history and tradition or in the original meaning of the Constitution.
At the same time, both Adkins and Dobbs provoked critics to denounce the
Supreme Court as illegitimate and to call for court reforms to curb the power
of the Court.
Two, both Adkins and Dobbs concerned the status of women and rejected arguments for
protecting them on the ground that doing so would be objectionably
paternalistic, given that the 19th Amendment had secured the right
of women to vote. In Adkins, in
response to arguments in support of a minimum wage law protecting women,
Sutherland retorted, “‘the revolutionary changes which have taken place...in
the contractual, political and civil status of women, culminating in the
Nineteenth amendment,’ have diminished nonphysical differences between the
sexes almost ‘to the vanishing point.’” (763) He inferred that, to guarantee
women a minimum wage that would restrict their liberty of contract “would be to
ignore all of the implications to be drawn from the present day trend of
legislation, as well as that of common thought and usage, by which woman is
accorded emancipation from the old doctrine that she must be given special
protection or be subjected to special restraint in her contractual or civil
relationships.” (763-64)
Similarly,
in Dobbs, in response to arguments in
support of a right to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy on the ground of
securing the status of equality for pregnant women, Justice Alito retorted,
“Women are not without electoral or political power.” He continued, “It is
noteworthy that the percentage of women who register to vote and cast ballots
is consistently higher than the percentage of men who do so.” Since women have the
right to vote, he reasons, if they want to protect their reproductive autonomy,
they can do so through “influencing public opinion, lobbying legislators,
voting, and running for office.” Thus, both cases invoked women’s right to vote
in rejecting the idea, in Sutherland’s words, that women “must be given special
protection” through constitutional law.
V. Conclusion
In these brief observations, I can hardly do justice to the rich insights and awesome erudition of Post’s The Taft Court. We are deeply indebted to him for shining a light on both the Taft Court and our own worrisomely similar Roberts Court.
jfleming@bu.edu. James E.
Fleming is The Honorable Paul J. Liacos Professor of Law at Boston University
School of Law.
James E. Fleming
In these brief observations, I can hardly do justice to the rich insights and awesome erudition of Post’s The Taft Court. We are deeply indebted to him for shining a light on both the Taft Court and our own worrisomely similar Roberts Court.