I am grateful to Jack Balkin for organizing this symposium
and to the commenters on Rationing the
Constitution for their close, careful, and generous engagement with my
book. Their wide-ranging posts raise more valuable and interesting points than
I can address here. I will therefore focus on four recurrent topics that strike
me as primary: (1) extensions, applications, and friendly amendments to my
judicial capacity model of Supreme Court decision-making; (2) the place of
judicial capacity in the legal process tradition; (3) the internal logic of the
judicial capacity model; and (4) causal inference and the problem of
observational equivalence.
To start, it will be helpful to restate the core claims of
the book. At least since Henry Hart’s famous 1958 Harvard Law Review Foreword, it has been well established that the
Supreme Court can decide only so many cases per year—150-200 at most. It is
also familiar wisdom that this limited capacity influences the Court’s
decisions and development of constitutional doctrine, albeit in diffuse and
indeterminate ways. Building on these foundations, Rationing the Constitution makes two novel claims: First, judicial
capacity limits have especially significant bite—and real predictive power—in many
of the most important constitutional domains, spanning federalism, separation
of powers, and individual rights. Second, these limits are the product not just
of limited time and resources but also, crucially, of widely shared judicial
norms. Chief among these is the Court’s felt need to review virtually all
lower-court decisions that invalidate federal statutes.
These core claims are the premises for my judicial capacity
model, which I spend most of the book attempting to substantiate using a
multiple case-study research design. In constitutional domains implicating a
large volume of federal statutes, this model predicts that the Supreme Court
will be strongly constrained to choose between some combination of strong
deference to the political process and hard-edged categorical rules. This, in
turn, limits the Court’s ability to challenge dominant political forces and
undermines its ability to competently resolve constitutional
controversies—categorical rules being generally too crude to sensibly define
the contours of federalism, separation of powers, equal protection, etc.
Judicial capacity is obviously not the only factor that
influences Supreme Court decision-making in these domains. Ideology, strategic
calculations, and legal principle all play important roles, too. But the judicial
capacity model helps to explain the pattern of post-New Deal Supreme Court
decisions in ways that none of these other factors can. Or so Rationing the Constitution contends. On
this contention, the book must stand or fall.
One final terminological clarification: When I use the term
judicial capacity, I mean the total volume of cases that the court system—and,
in particular, the Supreme Court—is capable of handling. I do not mean the
capacity of courts to produce reliably good decisions, which I shall call judicial competence. Nor do I mean the
capacity—or inclination—of courts to produce social change against the tide of
dominant political forces, which I shall call judicial independence.
Extensions, Applications,
and Friendly Amendments
In illuminating and complementary posts, David Marcus and
Aaron-Andrew Bruhl draw attention to judicial capacity issues in the lower
federal courts that I do not discuss at any length in my book. The focus of Rationing the Constitution is on the
relationship between judicial capacity and constitutional doctrine. And constitutional
doctrine is made, for the most part, in the Supreme Court. Moreover, through
the hierarchical system of precedent, the Court projects its
capacity-management decisions through the federal judiciary as a whole. But
Marcus and Bruhl helpfully demonstrate the payoffs of bringing lower courts
into the story—payoffs that both enrich and reinforce the judicial capacity
model.
As Bruhl points out, there is a substantial literature demonstrating that lower courts respond to caseload pressures by limiting oral argument, delegating decision-making authority to law clerks, and reviewing trial court decisions more deferentially. Bruhl does not cite specific examples, but highlights of this impressive body of work include William Richman & William Reynolds, Injustice on Appeal (2012); Bert Huang, “Lightened Scrutiny,” 124 Harv. L. Rev. 1109 (2011); and Marin Levy, “Judicial Attention as a Scarce Resource,” 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 401 (2013). To this list might be added Bruhl’s own “Deciding When to Decide,” 96 Cornell L. Rev. 203 (2011), an insightful case study of docket management in the U.S. Courts of Appeal after Blakely v. Washington (2004).
As Bruhl points out, there is a substantial literature demonstrating that lower courts respond to caseload pressures by limiting oral argument, delegating decision-making authority to law clerks, and reviewing trial court decisions more deferentially. Bruhl does not cite specific examples, but highlights of this impressive body of work include William Richman & William Reynolds, Injustice on Appeal (2012); Bert Huang, “Lightened Scrutiny,” 124 Harv. L. Rev. 1109 (2011); and Marin Levy, “Judicial Attention as a Scarce Resource,” 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 401 (2013). To this list might be added Bruhl’s own “Deciding When to Decide,” 96 Cornell L. Rev. 203 (2011), an insightful case study of docket management in the U.S. Courts of Appeal after Blakely v. Washington (2004).
Together, these scholars have persuasively shown that lower federal
courts are simultaneously under much more constant capacity pressure than the
Supreme Court and much more limited in the tools available to them to manage
this pressure. Unlike the Supreme Court, the lower courts cannot manage their
dockets by turning away cases. They also have limited flexibility to make
doctrine more deferential or rule-like. Laboring under such constraints, the
lower courts have had no choice but to compromise the minimum professional
standards—extensive oral argument; lengthy published opinions; little or no
delegation of actual decision-making to law clerks and administrative staff—that
Supreme Court justices have the luxury to treat as sacrosanct.
Indeed, in most legal domains, the Supreme Court’s
discretionary jurisdiction enables it to maintain these minimum professional
standards without much consideration of the volume of litigation its decisions
will invite down the road. Bruhl and Marcus discuss two such domains, vividly
demonstrating how differently the Supreme Court behaves outside of the
capacity-constrained domains discussed in my book. Bruhl focuses on the
void-for-vagueness doctrine and its application to federal sentencing laws in U.S. v. Johnson (2015), which led to
thousands of new filings in the federal district courts and courts of appeals. It
is impossible to imagine the Court issuing the same decision in a world where
it was compelled to review even ten percent of these new cases itself. But
because federal sentencing is a normal domain, one in which the Court is
content to leave all but a handful of cases to the lower courts, judicial
capacity did not substantially constrain its doctrinal options. The contrast
with capacity-constrained domains, where the Court feels compelled to review
virtually every lower court decision invalidating a federal law, is striking.
Marcus points to a different body of lower-court cases to
make a different point: “Components of dozens of state prison systems remain
under federal judicial supervision. In
recent decades, litigants have successfully sued dozens of state and city
foster care agencies, winning broad injunctive remedies for tens of thousands
of children. Federal judges play key
roles in the administration of disability policy in cities across the country.”
As Marcus recognizes, “[t]his litigation does not fall within the domains that
require intensive Court supervision. The Court can tolerate doctrinal mushiness
and whatever volume of litigation it invites when a lawsuit successfully
challenges the constitutionality of state law or local government policy
administration.” Yet this pattern of social reform litigation underscores an
important qualification to the judicial capacity model: The sharp limits that
judicial capacity imposes on judicial power extend only to capacity-constrained
domains.
Many of the most important constitutional domains fall into
this category, but not all of them. And in domains where the Court is content
to review only a small fraction of cases, the lower courts retain significant
freedom to deviate from the deference and categorical rules predicted by the
judicial capacity model in capacity-constrained domains. I believe this
qualification is implicit in the book, but Marcus is right to flag the “sweeping
intimations about the limits of federal judicial power that surface here and
there in Rationing the Constitution.”
These intimations should be read to apply solely to capacity-constrained
domains.
Adrian Vermeule’s comments are in a similar vein. While pronouncing
Rationing the Constitution “generally
admirable, clear, and correct,” he proposes three characteristically helpful
refinements in the form of “second-order complexities about the idea of
rationing judicial capacities.” I am happy to consider all of these as friendly
amendments, though I think Vermeule may overestimate their practical
significance.
First, Vermeule reframes the volume of litigation invited by
the Supreme Court’s doctrinal choices as an externality—a cost the Court’s
discretionary jurisdiction permits it to partially shift onto lower courts and
the bar. This reframing crisply captures the dynamic Bruhl noted in U.S. v. Johnson, where the Supreme
Court’s void-for-vagueness ruling buried the lower courts under an avalanche of
new sentencing challenges. Since this is a normal domain, the Court reviewed
only a tiny handful of these cases, leaving lower courts to bear nearly all of
the costs.
Even in capacity-constrained domains, where the Court feels
compelled to review a large fraction of cases, the Court can externalize some
of the costs of its doctrinal choices. The Court does not feel compelled to
review every lower court decision in any of these domains. In particular, it
does not feel compelled to review decisions invalidating state and local
legislation or decisions upholding federal statutes against constitutional
challenge. The costs of these cases are borne wholly by the lower courts. On
the other hand, what distinguishes capacity-constrained domains from normal
domains—their very sine qua non—is
the Court’s inability to avoid reviewing an overwhelmingly large fraction of
cases. (Usually, this inability is the product of the judicial norm requiring
the Court to review virtually every lower-court invalidation of a federal
statute.) In other words, these are domains in which the Court is forced to
internalize much of the cost of its doctrinal choices. In this sense,
Vermeule’s point about externalities is not so much a refinement of the
judicial capacity model as an incisive relabeling of its central underlying
mechanism.
Vermeule next points out that the Supreme Court may have the
power to expand its judicial capacity budget in a variety of ways, including through
its own constitutional decisions. If this is true, the Court’s “capacities may
then themselves be partly endogenous to judicial choices over time.” Vermeule
offers numerous potential examples. The most straightforward is “judicial
decisions approving administrative tribunals or legislative courts for workers’
compensation cases and routine bankruptcy matters.” But the list could go on at
great length. At a minimum, it would certainly include the Court’s restrictive modern
standing doctrine, the heightened pleading standards established in Bell Atlantic v. Twombly and Ashcroft v. Iqbal and decisions like U.S. v. Morrison that invalidate statutory
rights of action.
All of these decisions are significant, in their own right
and for their impact on the judicial capacity budget. Yet none changes the
fundamental reality on which the judicial capacity model is premised. In
capacity-constrained domains, the Court’s felt compulsion to review nearly
every lower-court invalidation of a federal statute sharply constrains the menu
of doctrinal options. As Vermeule correctly observes, this constraint is not an
inflexible law of nature. It cannot, however, be easily evaded without
sacrificing deeply rooted judicial commitments to minimum professional
standards and the uniformity of federal law.
Vermeule’s final suggested refinement is the most
interesting. He calls it “the warning shot,” and I cannot improve on his
elegant explanation: “The threat is stronger than the execution. While the
Court cannot do very much, the standing threat to override political decisions
anywhere potentially affects the anticipated reaction of institutions
everywhere.” The upshot is that the Supreme Court’s capacity limits may be less
significant than they seem. If the mere threat of judicial invalidation can
deter the political branches from acting, it is a mistake to view the Court’s
power solely in terms of the decisions it renders. One must also consider the
threat of further action that each decision implies and the reaction of
political actors to that threat.
I have no quarrel with Vermeule’s logic. The threat of
judicial invalidation may well have a broader restraining effect than would the
Court’s actual exercises of constitutional review. Like Marcus’s point about
social reform litigation in the lower federal courts, this is a valuable caveat
to my account of judicial capacity’s implications for judicial power. Still, I
am skeptical that this effect is of great practical import in
capacity-constrained domains, for two reasons. First, a threat that is never—or
almost never—carried out ceases to be credible at some point. The Court’s stark
record of deference in capacity-constrained domains, punctuated by a smattering
of narrow categorical rules, seems unlikely to keep members of Congress up at
night. Second, the history of federal legislation in these domains does not
suggest to me a Congress that is cowed into submission by the remote threat of
judicial review. Admittedly, this is an impressionistic judgment. Perhaps there
is some muted effect not visible to the naked eye, but I do not believe any
such effect is sufficient to undermine the book’s central conclusions.
To be clear, Vermeule does not actually argue the contrary.
He is careful to acknowledge that the threat is not always stronger than the
execution. His point is “merely that it can be, and the analyst always has to
consider whether it is.” To this theoretical point, I am happy to accede.
Judicial Capacity and
Legal Process
Maggie Blackhawk and Mariah Zeisberg both fault Rationing the Constitution for failing
to engage adequately with important prior scholarship. Zeisberg is bothered by
what she sees as my “false” and immodest claims to novelty. More substantively,
she thinks I ought to have mined the existing literature more thoroughly for
testable hypotheses that might compete with the judicial capacity model. She
offers the work of Alexander Bickel, Lawrence Sager, and Gerald Rosenberg as
illustrative examples. Blackhawk believes that a fuller engagement with the
legal process tradition could and should have made my judicial capacity model
more sensitive to the interplay between the Supreme Court and other
institutional actors.
I share Zeisberg’s esteem for Bickel, Sager, and Rosenberg,
as my citations to their work attest. It is also true that I am following in their
footsteps in the broad sense that Adrian Vermeule identifies when he writes
that Rationing the Constitution “develops
seamlessly out of a venerable line of work that considers constitutional theory
… in light of the capacities of judges and the resource constraints under which
they labor, especially constraints of time, attention, information, and
political capital.” On the other hand, Rationing
the Constitution is a very different kind of book from The Least Dangerous Branch, Justice
in Plainclothes, or The Hollow Hope.
Bickel and Sager both offer normative—or, more precisely, interpretive—accounts
of U.S. constitutional practice focused on judicial competence, democratic
legitimacy, and, in Bickel’s case, the risk of public backlash to unpopular
decisions. Neither devotes any substantial attention to judicial capacity, as I
use that term. Rosenberg’s account is positive, rather than normative, like Rationing the Constitution, but his
overwhelming focus is judicial independence, rather than judicial capacity.
This is not to suggest that my judicial capacity model lacks
intellectual antecedents. Richard Posner’s Federal
Courts: Crisis and Reform and Neil Komesar’s Imperfect Alternatives were the direct inspirations for my book and
supply the foundation on which it rests. Both address precisely the concept of
judicial capacity that is my focus in Rationing
the Constitution and explain the crucial role of judicial hierarchy in
limiting the capacity of the court system as a whole. But neither Posner nor
Komesar is concerned principally with constitutional law. The same is true of
Peter Strauss, whose article “One Hundred Fifty Cases a Year” was another
important inspiration and influence. For all of these reasons, I stand by my
claim that Rationing the Constitution
“is the first book-length work on constitutional law to take judicial capacity
seriously,” though it might have been better to say “the first systematic
examination of the influence of judicial capacity on U.S. constitutional
doctrine.”
Zeisberg’s more substantive complaint is that Rationing the Constitution overlooks a
goldmine of testable empirical hypotheses in the work of Bickel, Sager,
Rosenberg, and others. I do not doubt that an imaginative reader could generate
many testable hypotheses from this literature. The universe of such hypotheses,
as Zeisberg surely understands, is effectively limitless. But she does not
identify even one positive hypothesis that is (a) actually defended by a
prominent legal process theorist and (b) could plausibly explain the pattern of
Supreme Court decisions discussed in Rationing
the Constitution better than the judicial capacity model. Nor am I aware of
any hypothesis that satisfies both of these criteria.
The two examples Zeisberg cites, drawn from Rosenberg and
Bickel, are both normative rather than positive claims. The “hypothesis” she
derives from Rosenberg is illustrative: “Courts concerned with capacity should time their major interventions in
ways that are supported, rather than blocked, by the other branches” (my
emphasis). Rosenberg makes no such normative claim, but he most certainly does
not make the positive claim that courts actually do time their interventions in this way. Indeed, the major evidence
for his thesis that courts are incapable of spearheading social change consists
of failed judicial attempts to overcome political resistance.
For these reasons, I chose to focus my analysis of the
judicial capacity model on the competing models of judicial decision-making
that are most widely and vigorously advocated in the existing literature. I do
not claim to have shown that the judicial capacity model dominates all
potential alternatives. I do not even claim that the judicial capacity model
dominates the leading models I compare it to in the book as to all features of Supreme Court decision-making. I claim only
that it is capable of explaining some of those features better than those
alternative models. Given the wide influence of the legalist, attitudinalist,
and strategic models, this is strong evidence in favor of the judicial capacity
model, though Zeisberg is surely right that there is more work to be done.
Maggie Blackhawk’s critique is more limited, and her
comments also have a constructive dimension. While recognizing the judicial
capacity model as “valid and valuable,” she suggests that greater engagement
with the legal process tradition would have made the model stronger. More
specifically, she cites the work of Henry Hart & Albert Sacks, Phil
Frickey, and William Eskridge for the proposition that the Supreme Court does
not operate in an institutional vacuum. This is certainly correct and important,
as is Blackhawk’s narrower point that the behavior of the political branches
influences the prospective volume of litigation. As I explain in the book, “significant
political opposition” to the Court’s constitutional decisions in
capacity-constrained domains “tends to produce a high volume of litigation that
taxes the limits of judicial capacity.” It is in this sense that judicial
capacity helps to explain the Court’s limited ability to challenge dominant
political forces.
Yet the opposite is also true, as Blackhawk points out: If
dominant political forces welcome aggressive judicial review, as they sometimes
do, judicial capacity might operate as less of a constraint. Instead of
litigating vigorously up to the Supreme Court, the government might simply
refuse to defend broad swaths of legislation against constitutional challenge.
In theory, this could allow the Court to announce stringent new limitations on
federal legislation without inviting much litigation that it would feel
compelled to review. This is an astute and valuable point; Blackhawk is right
that I could—and perhaps should—have done more to develop it.
On the other hand, I suspect its practical import is quite
limited, for two reasons. First, in most capacity-constrained domains, it would
be difficult for the Supreme Court to articulate broad constitutional limits on
federal legislative authority without goring quite a few oxen on both sides of
the political spectrum. Second, even when the government refuses to defend
legislation challenged as unconstitutional, other interested parties will often
have standing to step in and litigate in the government’s stead. Think of the
challenge to the Affordable Care Act currently pending in Texas, which the
Trump administration has refused to defend. At any rate, I am unaware of any
capacity-constrained domain in which the political branches have engaged in
sufficiently broad acquiescence to eliminate—or even substantially weaken—the constraints
of judicial capacity.
One possible exception, suggested by Blackhawk, is the constitutional
prohibition on sex discrimination, which the Solicitor General famously opposed,
in part, on judicial capacity grounds. Hundreds of federal laws on the books at
the time discriminated on the basis of sex. Yet no flood of cases materialized
that the Supreme Court felt compelled to review. The judicial capacity model
offers a partial explanation. The constitutional prohibition on sex and
discrimination hardened into a virtual per se rule quite quickly—a mere five
years elapsed between Reed v. Reed
and Craig v. Boren—rendering the
outcome of most cases a foregone conclusion. (More on this general dynamic
below.) But Blackhawk is right to suggest that the women’s movement is a
crucial part of the story, both in triggering doctrinal change and in shaping
social attitudes to reduce the need for litigation. This point is fully
compatible with the judicial capacity model and indeed strengthens it, as
Blackhawk suggests.
The Logic of Judicial
Capacity
Aziz Huq and Mariah Zeisberg raise different but overlapping
objections to the internal logic of my judicial capacity model. Huq questions
my definition of capacity-constrained domains; my contention that judicial
capacity tends systematically toward deference; and the relationship between
categorical rules and the volume of litigation. Zeisberg makes a similar point
about categorical rules and also questions whether my model generates
falsifiable predictions. I believe all of these questions are answered in the
book, though perhaps not as clearly as they should have been if they did not
register with readers as perceptive as Huq and Zeisberg.
Capacity-constrained domains are those in which judicial
capacity strongly constrains the Supreme Court to employ some combination of
strong deference and categorical rules. Examples discussed in the book include
the commerce power, the spending power, the nondelegation doctrine,
presidential administration, the equal protection clause, and regulatory
takings. Conceptually, I suggest that capacity-constrained domains come in two
basic flavors—high-volume and high-stakes. In the former, the sheer
volume of potential litigation is what constrains the Court’s doctrinal
choices. In the latter, the principal constraint comes from the high fraction
of prospective cases in which the Court would feel compelled to grant review. Some
domains fall into both of these categories; I call this third set hybrid domains.
As I explain in the book, this three-part framework is meant
as a heuristic: “What ultimately matters is the number of potential cases in
which the Supreme Court would feel compelled to grant review. This number is
inevitably and always a function of both stakes and volume.” For example,
neither the Fourth Amendment nor Title VII qualifies as a capacity-constrained
domain, even though both involve thousands of actual and potential cases per
year. The reason is simple: the Court feels compelled to review only a tiny
fraction of these cases; therefore, neither of these domains is likely to overwhelm
the Court’s limited capacity.
A parallel point holds for something like the Emoluments
Clause. The Court is likely to feel compelled to review every successful
Emoluments Clause challenge—a very high fraction of cases—but no plausible
interpretation of that clause is likely to invite a large enough volume of
litigation to tax the Court’s capacity. Thus, the Emoluments Clause is not a
capacity-constrained domain.
The Commerce Clause is different. The volume of potential
litigation is probably smaller than the existing volume of Fourth Amendment and
Title VII litigation. But the Supreme Court feels compelled to review virtually
every lower court decision invalidating a federal statute. As such, even a hundred
successful commerce-clause suits per year would severely tax the Court’s
limited capacity. Other capacity-constrained domains—like Equal Protection and
regulatory takings—implicate preponderantly state and local laws, which the
Court does not feel compelled to review in large numbers. But these domains
also implicate federal laws, whose invalidation the Court does feel compelled
to review. This, together with the large potential volume of litigation, brings
Equal Protection and takings within the ambit of the judicial capacity model.
I hope this clears up Huq’s mistaken impression that volume
is doing all of the heavy lifting in the judicial capacity model. If anything,
stakes—the fraction of cases the Court feels compelled to review—are more
important. This explains why the book focuses so heavily on the invalidation of
federal statutes, which is the next question Huq raises. In theory, a large
enough volume of statutory cases or constitutional cases involving the actions
of individual executive officials could pose a threat to the Supreme Court’s
limited capacity. But the fraction of such cases that the Court feels compelled
to review is so low that this is hard to imagine in practice. Huq points out
that nothing in the Court’s formal rules gives precedence to cases involving
federal statutes, but David Marcus gets this right: “no observer of the Court
could plausibly doubt that [this] commitment exists.”[1]
Contrary to Huq’s intimation, this is a purely positive observation about the
Court’s certiorari practice, not a normative one about how that practice should
operate.
As the book explains, this feature of the Court’s practice is
also contingent, rather than necessary. Huq is correct that the justices might alter
or abandon it, perhaps out of frustration with the limits of judicial capacity.
In theory, the justices might also decide to delegate much greater
decision-making authority to law clerks or to eschew written opinions or even
to decide cases by coin flip. Any of these changes would enable the Supreme
Court to decide far more cases and perhaps some of these changes will
eventually come to pass. But the professional norms undergirding the judicial
capacity model have functioned as fixed stars of Supreme Court administration
from at least the New Deal era. No significant change seems likely in the near
term.
Huq next points out that categorical rules can be intrusive
as well as deferential: “No federal rule-making with the force of law,” for
instance. This is correct and fully consistent with the judicial capacity model.
In fact, Chapter 11 discusses Huq’s precise example as an illustration of
judicial capacity’s impact on the constitutional choice set: “[S]weeping
reforms” like Philip Hamburger’s proposal to abolish binding administrative
rules “might be consistent with the limits of judicial capacity, due to their
starkly categorical character, but nevertheless worse than the disease they
were intended to cure.” Thus far, most of the justices have considered sweeping
categorical limits too unpalatable to embrace in most capacity-constrained
domains. The limits of judicial capacity have therefore generally compelled the
Supreme Court to adopt categorically deferential rules like the rational basis
test, supplemented by the occasional and narrow categorical limit like Clinton v. New York’s prohibition on
line-item vetoes.
Of course, the preferences of the justices on this score
could always change. If they do, judicial capacity could conceivably push the
Court toward more sweeping interventions than the justices would adopt in a
world without capacity constraints. I explicitly note this possibility in the
book. Still, it strikes me as more theoretical than real. The types of sweeping
rules Huq has in mind would be extraordinarily disruptive and would, in many
cases, represent an incredibly crude mechanism for achieving their underlying
purposes. Even with a significant ideological shift, the probability of the
Court adopting sweeping constitutional limits of this character seems quite
low. Nor would such limits offer ironclad security against a judicial capacity
overload. Lochner era limits on
federal legislative power were largely categorical in nature. Yet their
sweeping scope led more than 100 federal district judges to issue more than
1,600 injunctions against New Deal legislation in the summer of 1935 alone. Had
the Court not retreated from these limits in 1937, it is doubtful how much
longer it could have borne the strain.
Huq’s final point, echoed by Zeisberg, is that categorical
rules themselves may prove malleable and unpredictable and therefore fail to
inoculate the Court against capacity overload. To illustrate this point, Huq
and Zeisberg both point to the economic/noneconomic distinction of Lopez and Morrison and the activity/inactivity distinction of NFIB v. Sebelius. I hold no brief for
either of these decisions or the wisdom of the rules they embrace. But the
important point for the judicial capacity model is that both clearly insulated
the vast majority of federal legislation against constitutional challenge. They
did so not through the intrinsic clarity or precision of the categorical
distinctions they employed, but by clearly signaling that those distinctions
imposed extraordinarily narrow limits on federal power. This signaling was explicit
in Chief Justice Roberts’s insistence in NFIB
that the Affordable Care Act was the only federal law in history to regulate
economic inactivity. It was implicit in Lopez’s
reaffirmation of Wickard v. Filburn
on the ground that consumption of home-grown wheat counts as economic activity.
The clarity of these signals did not deter all
entrepreneurial litigators, but for almost 10 years after Morrison, the Courts of Appeals rejected every commerce-power
challenge they heard, and the Supreme Court denied review. When the Ninth
Circuit finally broke this pattern in Gonzales
v. Raich, the Court reversed in a belt-and-suspenders opinion that defined
economic activity with sweeping breadth. The Court also reinvigorated the
rational basis test and the necessary and proper clause as alternative grounds
for upholding federal legislative power. In dissent, Justice O’Connor accused
the majority of using “a dictionary definition of economics to skirt the real
problem of drawing a meaningful line between ‘what is national and what is
local.’” She was exactly right, and this is just what the judicial capacity
model would predict. It is too early to assess the legacy of NFIB v. Sebelius, but the preliminary
evidence suggests a strikingly parallel story.
Finally, Zeisberg asks what it would take to falsify the
judicial capacity model and suggests that the Court’s adoption of the
conceptually malleable commerce power tests discussed above should count as
falsification. I tried to be as explicit on this point as possible: In
capacity-constrained domains, “the judicial capacity model predicts that the
court will be strongly constrained to
employ some combination of deference and categorical rules such that the government will almost always win,
or the application of the Court’s test
will almost always be readily predictable by judges or litigants, or both.
This prediction is obviously not perfectly precise and its content will vary to
some extent by context. Nevertheless, it is quite demanding and easily
falsifiable.” For the reasons explained above, I believe the Court’s recent
commerce-power decisions are fully consistent with the judicial capacity model.
Indeed, they are some of its best illustrations.
Causal Inference and
Observational Equivalence
Establishing the consistency of the judicial capacity model
with the Supreme Court’s decisions is the easy part. The far more difficult
question is how to disentangle the causal role of judicial capacity from other
competing explanations for the pattern of Supreme Court decisions in
capacity-constrained domains. If one or more of those explanations is equally
consistent with the Court’s decisions, how is one to adjudicate between them? This
is the problem of observational equivalence, and it is an extremely thorny one.
Frederick Schauer, Victoria Nourse, and Mariah Zeisberg all raise probing
questions on this front. In response, I am tempted to quote Philip Roth,
quoting Joe Louis: “I did the best I could with what I had.” Causal inference
is exceedingly tricky, no research design is perfect, and no single study can
realistically aspire to be definitive. But I believe the methodological choices
in Rationing the Constitution were
well-justified and that the book supplies strong evidence to support the
judicial capacity model.
To explain this belief, I must address two distinct
questions raised by the commenters. The first, emphasized by Schauer and
Nourse, is whether valid causal inference requires comparison of
capacity-constrained domains with normal domains. The answer is no.
Any consideration of this question must start with the
crucial premise that case studies employ a different kind of causal inference
from that employed by statistical analysis, contra the work of King et al. cited by Schauer. Rather than
patterns of co-variation across independent and dependent variables, causal
inference in case research is based on “the match between what empirical
evidence we would hypothesize that the [causal] mechanism should leave and what
we actually find in the case.”[2] (Some
older qualitative approaches—such as Mill’s method and its various offshoots—do
attempt to draw causal inferences from variance across small numbers of cases,
but these approaches are now widely viewed as suspect when used for this
purpose.) This explains why some case-study researchers prefer the terms
“causal condition” and “outcome” to “independent” and “dependent variables.”
Within a given case, neither the value of the causal condition nor the value of
the outcome actually varies. Instead, a causal condition, such as limited
judicial capacity, either does or does not cause a particular outcome, such as
deference or categorical rules.
From this account of “within-case” causal inference, it
follows that the rationale for studying multiple cases is not to examine
variation across cases—for instance, in the frequency of categorical rules or
deferential decisions across capacity-constrained and normal domains. Instead,
the reason for studying multiple cases is to identify the bounds of the
population in which a given causal inference—made within individual cases,
rather than across them—holds. For this purpose, the only relevant cases are
those in which the causal condition (or the corresponding value of the
independent variable) is present. Here that means the capacity-constrained
domains in which the judicial capacity model predicts that the limits of
judicial capacity will strongly constrain Supreme Court decision-making.
Within this category, the latest qualitative methods
literature recommends studying as broad and diverse a range of cases as
possible. The greater the number and diversity of cases in which a causal
inference holds, “the better we are able to infer [that] what was found in the
chosen cases should also be present in other typical cases throughout the
population.”[3] As
such, the case studies in Rationing the
Constitution encompass a broad and diverse range of capacity-constrained
domains, but no normal domains, since the causal condition on which the
judicial capacity model is premised is not present in those domains. This method
amounts to selecting on the independent variable (or causal condition), not the
dependent variable, as Schauer suggests. It does not produce selection bias
because its goal is not to generate a representative sample of the general
population of cases, but rather to identify the subset of that population in
which a causal inference drawn from individual cases holds.
This is not to suggest that normal domains are completely
irrelevant to the judicial capacity model. Schauer is correct that a close examination
of domains in which the Supreme Court is not constrained by judicial capacity
could “tell us something about” the model’s generalizability. The symposium
contributions of David Marcus and Aaron Bruhl are good examples, illustrating
that the Supreme Court feels far freer to employ mushy, non-deferential
standards in (at least some) normal domains than it does in
capacity-constrained domains. Many other examples could be adduced to the same
effect. A systematic examination of such domains would certainly be valuable
and could help to more clearly mark the boundary between capacity-constrained
domains, where the judicial capacity model applies, and normal domains, where
it does not. But this was beyond what I could undertake in a single book. Its
omission does not affect the strength of the causal inference in the domains I
discuss, merely the extent to which that inference can be generalized beyond
those domains.
Schauer is also correct that the judicial capacity model
needs to account for “those instances in which the alleged causal agent was
present but for which the hypothesized effect was not present.” Nourse puts the
same point more concretely: Coan “must explain variance”—i.e., capacity-constrained
domains “in which high capacity does not yield the bright line rule, or
deference.” If there were capacity-constrained domains in which the model’s
predictions did not hold, this would indeed be a problem requiring explanation.
If no satisfactory explanation were available, the existence of such domains
would falsify the model.
Fortunately for the model, there are no such domains, at
least not that I am aware of. The possible examples suggested by Schauer—the
dormant commerce clause, the establishment clause, the “time, place, and
manner” branch of free speech doctrine, and Daubert
v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. (1993)—are all normal domains in which
the Supreme Court feels perfectly comfortable denying review in virtually all
cases. This is largely because the Court’s decisions in these areas threaten
few—and, in the case of Daubert and dormant commerce, no—federal laws. In this sense, these
domains are similar to the void-for-vagueness and social reform cases discussed
by Bruhl and Marcus. Far from undercutting the judicial capacity model, they
vividly illustrate how much freer the Supreme Court feels to employ vague,
non-deferential standards outside of capacity-constrained domains.
This still leaves the question of observational equivalence.
As Schauer and Zeisberg observe, judicial deference could be explained by a legalist
commitment to judicial restraint, rather than judicial capacity. It is true
that such a commitment—which might be grounded in democratic legitimacy or
institutional competence—could explain any given deferential decision. It
almost certainly does explain the deference embraced by at least some of the
justices some of the time. But most of the legalist literature on judicial
restraint is normative, rather than positive. I am aware of no significant
positive theory of judicial behavior predicting that Supreme Court justices
will systematically behave deferentially over long stretches of time out of a
legalist commitment to judicial restraint. Even if there were such a theory, it
could not easily explain the Court’s occasional willingness to invalidate
federal legislative action in capacity-constrained domains using categorical
rules.
Of course, the Court’s use of such rules might be explained
by a complementary legalist commitment to rule-bound decision-making, grounded
in administrative convenience or predictability. But like the literature on
judicial restraint, the legalist literature touting the virtues of rules is
primarily normative, rather than positive. A principled commitment to these
virtues might explain why some justices employ categorical rules some of the
time. But this literature supplies no convincing reason to expect that the
Court would systematically employ categorical rules, rather than standards,
when invalidating government action in capacity-constrained domains. If anything,
as Adrian Vermeule points out, the Court in general has an incentive to
over-produce vague standards, which “externalize the costs of uncertainty onto
litigants and lower courts.” This incentive disappears—or is at least greatly
reduced—in capacity-constrained domains where the Court feels compelled to
review a large fraction of the litigation generated by vague standards. This is
why the judicial capacity model predicts that the Court will seldom invalidate
government action in these domains except in the form of categorical rules,
which is exactly what the evidence shows.
To be sure, there are cross-cutting incentives for the
justices to employ categorical rules, many of them relating to the effective
control of lower courts. These incentives are the subject of a small but
growing positive literature on rules and standards. But as I summarize in the
book, “the only prediction
that [these models] support is that the choice of doctrinal form will be
unpredictable.” They cannot, therefore, explain why the Supreme Court would
exhibit a stable and predictable preference for rules when invalidating
government action in capacity-constrained domains.
To sum
up, there is obviously some overlap between the predictions of the judicial capacity
model and legalist commitments to judicial restraint and categorical rules. Legalist
commitments do not predict the systematic deference or embrace of categorical
rules that the judicial capacity model does, but they do predict some judges
will defer to the democratic process or employ categorical rules some of the
time. To the extent that this prediction overlaps with the predictions of judicial
capacity model, it represents a case of observational equivalence. The evidence
is consistent with both models and is therefore uniquely explained by neither.
The
upshot is that some—though not all—of the Supreme Court’s deference and
rule-bound decisions in capacity-constrained domains could be the product of legalist
commitments. Alternatively, this pattern of decisions might be the product of
judicial capacity limits, or it might be the joint product of both judicial
capacity and legal principle. The available evidence is consistent with all of
these possibilities. Yet the judicial capacity model still stands alone in its
power to explain the Supreme Court’s systematic deference in
capacity-constrained domains and the Court’s unwillingness to depart from such
deference except in the form of hard-edged categorical rules. There is much
more to be said on this subject, but I have already gone on far too long. I
refer any interested readers to Chapter 12 of Rationing the Constitution,
especially pages 182-86.
I will
close where I began, by thanking all of the symposium participants for their
thought-provoking contributions and Jack Balkin for organizing. This discussion
has given me a great deal to think about and much grist for future work. I hope
others will join me in carrying the project forward.
[1] See also
Justice Elena Kagan on Supreme Court and
Constitutional Law, C-SPAN (Aug. 31, 2016),
https://www.c-span.org/video/?414445-1/justice-elena-kagan-supreme-court-constitutional-law
(“[A]nytime another court invalidates a federal statute, we’ll always take that
case . . . on the theory that Congress’s statutes shouldn’t be invalidated,
except by us, that we’re the only court that gets to do that in the end.”); H.W. Perry, Jr., Deciding to Decide: Agenda
Setting in the United States Supreme Court 2949-50 (ebook 1991).
[2] Derek Beach & Rasmus Brun Pedersen, Causal
Case Study Methods: Foundations and Guidelines for Comparing, Matching, and
Tracing 116 (2016); see also Gary Goertz, Multimethod Research, Causal
Mechanisms, and Case Studies 89 (2017); Gary
Goertz & James Mahoney, A Tale of Two Cultures: Qualitative and
Quantitative Research in the Social Sciences (2012); Alexander L. George & Andrew Bennett, Case
Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences (2005).
[3] Brun
& Pedersen, supra, at 549.