The fact that it is Judge Gorsuch, rather than Judge
Garland, for whom confirmation hearings are now underway prompts a return to
the question of whether the Supreme Court is capable of doing little more than
reflecting the preferences of political majorities.
Over the last decade, it became
fashionable (first in the academy, then among journalists) to press the view that
Supreme Court decisions cannot and do not stray far from the policy preferences
of political majorities. My friend and
colleague Barry Friedman’s one-volume history of the Court, The Will of the People (2009), played a
major role in re-invigorating this line of commentary about the Court.
If
you think the Gorsuch/Garland difference is likely to be a significant one for
Court decisions, what does that suggest about where “the majoritarian thesis” goes
awry? Here, I want to suggest at least
two places, which the current context helps illuminate. The first is the role of historical
contingency, in both politics and Court vacancies.
The most likely mechanism through which
the Court might be expected to reflect the views of political majorities is
through the appointments process. But
since we do not have a structure through which Supreme Court vacancies occur at
regularly recurring intervals, there is a great deal of randomness about how
many appointments, if any, any particular President gets to make. President Nixon, for example, made four
appointments between 1969-1972, which shaped the Court for decades. Yet there are Presidents in the modern era
who have served one term without being able to make any appointments at
all. Jimmy Carter had none, and George
W. Bush had none in his first four years.
Donald Trump, of course, entered office with a vacant seat awaiting
him. And since Justices are appointed
younger and serve much longer these days, there is a great deal of luck
involved as to whether even two-term Presidents can re-shape the Court in their
image. Up until 1970, a two-term
President appointed nearly 5 Justices on average, or a majority of the Court;
but since then, that figure has dropped to 2.7 Justices, on average.
Politics and elections themselves, of course,
are also highly contingent, as this fall’s election also should remind us. Donald Trump won an electoral majority, but
not a popular majority. Even assuming a
Justice he appoints reflects the substantive preferences of his electoral
constituency, what does that tell us about whether that Justice’s positions
reflect “the majority’s preferences”? Beyond
that, if the Democrats had found their way to a different candidate, would the
outcome of the election have been the same?
Who knows? And had Justice Scalia
died three months earlier (or six) so that President Obama had
filled the seat, matters would be very different for that reason as well. The point is that when the country is so
closely and sharply divided, small differences in politics and elections can be
highly consequential, yet have enormous consequences for Court appointments.
The second reason to be skeptical
about the idea that the Court is highly constrained to do little more than
reflect the preferences of political majorities is that on many issues, the
very idea of “the majority” is so nebulous as to make this claim hard to give
content to. Most of the “majoritarian”
claims about the Court never tell us what majority the Court is supposedly
reflecting. Is it the political majorities
in Congress, which in theory have power to respond to Court decisions (if government
is not itself divided)? Or is it the “popular
majority” as reflected in something like national public-opinion surveys? Indeed, a lot of recent political science research
suggests that our political bodies do not even reflect the view of popular
majorities.
On some issues, people’s views are
unsettled, fluid, and highly responsive to the way political elites – including
the Court in its decisions – frame the issues.
So “the majority” sometimes follows the actions of public institutions, including
the Court, rather than constrains or determines those actions. And because the
country is so intensely, yet closely, divided on other issues, there simply is
not any dominant majority by which the Court could be constrained. The Court can make decisions in either
direction and find support from some large, strong faction of the public who
likes the outcomes.
In the
wake of Citizens United, I wrote an
article raising some of these challenges, which was titled Is
the Supreme Court a “Majoritarian” Institution? Justin Driver has written good critiques
along similar lines. Campaign finance is
a good test of the claim that the Court is destined to do little more than
reflect the views of “popular majorities.”
Do the Court’s campaign finance decisions, which strike down legislation
enacted by national or state majorities, do that? I don’t put a lot of stock in public-opinion
polls, though it seems the “majoritarian thesis” requires us to do that; but
those polls purportedly show large majorities that reject these decisions (that
does not make these decisions right or wrong, as a legal matter, of course). It’s not necessary, though, to go even that
far. The country might be deeply divided
on campaign finance without a clear majority one way or the other. The Court has a lot of room for freedom of
action in this area, as in many others, regardless of what “public opinion”
might be.
Yes, it is true that Court decisions are inevitably affected by broad shifts in culture over time. If there are clear majorities, sustained over long enough periods of time, the Court will come to reflect a dominant political sensibility of an era. If you look at the Supreme Court from a 10,000 foot altitude, perhaps that is all you will see. But historical contingency affects the Court, as it does all other institutions, and the current confirmation process provides a dramatic reminder of that.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.