Yesterday I responded
to Rick Hills, who has been writing
about progressives’ new-found
love of federalism.
Today I want to respond to Ilya
Somin’s spirited critique of my
views on federalism.
Ilya argues that if you believe, as
I do, that state and local power serves an
important role in a well-functioning democracy, you should favor a sovereignty
model of federalism, one that involves judicially enforced constraints on
federal power. Ilya’s point is a serious
one and highly intuitive. If you think
state power plays a useful role in our democracy, why shouldn’t judges protect
that power? On this view, just as the
First Amendment protects dissenting speech, so too should the Constitution
protect what I’ve called “dissenting
by deciding” by shielding outlier state policies
from national reversal.
Despite the appeal of
Ilya’s argument, I disagree with him for three reasons. The first is a pragmatic one, familiar to
anyone who has taken constitutional law.
Despite the best efforts of the Rehnquist and Roberts Courts, judicial
efforts to hold back the tide of federal power have been a failure. As I’ve written elsewhere,
the federal government has a readymade work-around for every pro-federalism
ruling that the Court has imposed. The nationalists have lost battles, to be sure — Shelby County
v. Holder being the most heartbreaking defeat — but they are undoubtedly winning the war.
The Court could, of course, try to do more to limit federal
power, but the costs associated with those strategies have proved to be too
high even for this conservative set of Justices. The game is just not worth the candle.
Second,
Ilya and I have a fundamentally different view of what a well-functioning
democracy should look like. Nationalists
like myself have always worried about a sovereignty model because it
facilitates a retreat from national norms; that’s why slavery and Jim Crow loom
so large in federalism debates. It’s
worth remembering that those who favor federalism today generally agree upon a
baseline of rights. But a nationalist should
still worry about a model of state power that depends on sovereignty and
separation, one that imagines us settling into our all-too-comfortable
red and blue enclaves rather than interacting with one
another. My own
model of democracy is more nationally oriented and decidedly
more agonistic. I value states because
they tee up the conflicts and debates that forge
national norms rather than allow us to shield ourselves from the federal
policies with which we disagree. For
these and other reasons, I envision states as part of an integrated national
system and believe that if the national government wants to play the national
supremacy trump card, it can.
This
brings me to the third key difference between Ilya’s account and my own: I think that sovereignty is unnecessary for
states to play this important role in our democracy. That’s because, as Jason Weinstein-Tull has quipped, the Supremacy Clause trump card turns out to be a jack. Ilya assumes that for states to be powerful,
they must preside over their own empires, wielding power separate and apart
from the national government. But states
need not wield the power of the sovereign to serve as sources of resistance and
change. Instead, they can wield what
I’ve called the “power
of the servant.”
The federal government lacks the resources and manpower to implement its
own policies. As a result, it depends
heavily on states and localities to administer federal law. That dependence, in turn, empowers the states
to resist federal policy and engage in what Jessica Bulman-Pozen and I have
called “uncooperative
federalism.”
By serving as agents of the national government, implementing federal
policy from within rather than challenging it from without, states can
influence national policy in
a number of important ways.
That’s
not to say that courts should play no role in refereeing federal-state
relations. But rather than policing the
boundaries of state and federal regulatory arenas, as the sovereignty model
suggests, courts should ensure fair bargaining conditions between the states
and federal government. That sounds like
an old point – indeed, it’s precisely the aim of process federalism. But process federalism rests an
outdated set of assumptions about the nature of state power. It makes
perfect sense to look primarily to politics to safeguard healthy federal-state
relations and to focus on the second-order policing of federal-state bargaining
rather than the first-order policing of federal-state boundaries. But process federalists’ core argument is
that states
will leverage their connections to federal officials in order to protect
state autonomy. Process federalists’
assumption, in other words, is that federalisms’ end goal is for the states and
federal governments to be engaged in the governance equivalent of parallel
play.