For the Symposium on the Constitution and Economic Inequality
This paper focuses on the crucial elements of post-Civil War constitutionalism scholars miss when they give the place of pride to the Civil Rights Act at the expense of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill. The Republicans who framed the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill understood that judicial action could not eradicate slavery. Their legislative and constitutional program recognized that persons could transition from slaves to full citizens only if Congress aggressively exercised national power under Section 2 of the Thirteenth Amendment. Legislation was necessary to provide former slaves with various goods and services, the precise provision of which depending on local circumstances and changing conditions. Given the need for a high degree of nimbleness in the managing of that transition, entrenching crucial features of the Freedmen’s Bureau Bill in a constitutional amendment that would be enforced by the federal judiciary made little sense. Instead, the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill was drafted by Republicans who understood that Congress rather than the judiciary was expected to play the lead role in removing all badges and incidents of slavery in American constitutional life.
This paper focuses on the crucial elements of post-Civil War constitutionalism scholars miss when they give the place of pride to the Civil Rights Act at the expense of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill. The Republicans who framed the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill understood that judicial action could not eradicate slavery. Their legislative and constitutional program recognized that persons could transition from slaves to full citizens only if Congress aggressively exercised national power under Section 2 of the Thirteenth Amendment. Legislation was necessary to provide former slaves with various goods and services, the precise provision of which depending on local circumstances and changing conditions. Given the need for a high degree of nimbleness in the managing of that transition, entrenching crucial features of the Freedmen’s Bureau Bill in a constitutional amendment that would be enforced by the federal judiciary made little sense. Instead, the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill was drafted by Republicans who understood that Congress rather than the judiciary was expected to play the lead role in removing all badges and incidents of slavery in American constitutional life.
The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill was also designed to
prevent white persons from making transitions from freedom to dependency. Sections 3-6 of that bill provided both
freedmen and destitute refugees with various goods and services. Republican supporters of this provisions emphasized
that Congress had the obligation to act for the general welfare and that
preventing the dependency inherent in economic destitution justified
legislative action. As significantly,
Republicans were as inclined to justify the provision of goods and services to
white persons who had never been slaves under Section 2 of the Thirteenth
Amendment. Their arguments for the
constitutionality of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill insisted that a minimum
degree of economic security and education was a central condition of freedom
and full citizenship.
Restoring the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill to the core
of Reconstruction explains some features of the post-Civil War Amendments,
while challenging other shibboleths of American constitutionalism. Commentary on the post-Civil War Amendments
begins by acknowledging that the text speaks in generalities, but fails to
appreciate the institutional logic of that language. Republicans did not ratify a precise legal
code because they recognized that Congress needed substantial discretion to
determine the policies that best ensured that persons of color transitioned
from slavery to enjoying the full rights of citizens of a free republic and
not, as often maintained, because they could not agree on specifics or were more
interested in moral exhortation that precise legal norms. Contrary to Richard Posner and William
Rehnquist, the Constitution of the United States is not a charter of negative
liberties. The Second Freedmen’s Bureau
Bill’s Constitution is committed to ensuring the national government has the
power necessary to act for the general welfare and, as such, is more an
instrument for preventing local and private tyranny than for limiting
government. Reconstruction Republicans
believed that national government under the Thirteenth Amendment had duties to
provide goods and services to destitute citizens and freedmen who need
government assistance making the transition for slavery to independent
citizen. Finally, the debates over the
Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill highlight the perversity of contemporary
constitutional decisions which insist that the federal judiciary is the
institution primarily responsible for implementing the post-Civil War
amendments. Republicans when defending
the constitutionality of the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill uniformly insisted
that Congress was the institution constitutionally charged with guaranteeing
those positive rights, not the Supreme Court of the United States. More precisely, the Republican Party had the
place of constitutional honor. The
post-Civil War Amendments were framed at a time when the dominant party were
considered the primary vehicle for ensuring constitutional fidelity. Republicans in the Thirty-Eighth Congress
assumed that their party, not any particular institution, was the institution
that determined the measures constitutionally necessary to realize the promise
of the Thirteenth and, later, Fourteenth Amendments. Their arguments on the Second
Freedmen’s Bureau Bill highlight the crucial features of American
constitutionalism that judges, governing officials, lawyers and citizens miss
when they look at the Constitution through the modern lens of judicial
supremacy.
The Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill’s Constitution provides
a distinctive perspective on economic inequalities and American
constitutionalism. The persons
responsible for the original Constitution and post-Civil War Constitution were
concerned with economic inequalities or at least economic rights, but their
concerns are not explicitly manifested in the text of the Constitution. The Constitution of 1789 and the Constitution
of 1868 do not enumerate economic rights because their framers regarded
constitutions as empowering rather than as disabling mechanisms. Contemporary Americans assume that
constitutions protect rights by enumerating limits on government power and
empowering the national judiciary to enforce those restrictions. The persons responsible for the Constitution
of 1789 believed that rights were best protected by structuring government
institutions so that elite leaders would have the combination of interests,
values and capacities that would lead them to protect rights. The persons responsible for the post-Civil
War Constitution believed rights were best protected when the party of the
majority of the people who remained loyal during the Civil War controlled all
three branches of the national government.
The Republicans responsible for the Second Freedmen’s Bureau Bill and
the post-Civil War Constitution believed destitution and dependency were forms
of slavery that the national legislature was constitutionally obligated to
alleviate under the Thirteenth Amendment.
Once we understand the Republican commitment to economic rights and the
way in which the constitution promoted those rights, we can see how the
Constitution of 1868 in many ways was better structured to place economic
inequality and dependency at the core of American constitutionality than the
judicially driven constitutionalism of the present.