JB: Your last two books were on constitutional structure.
Why did you decide to a series of commentaries on the essays in The Federalist?
SL: Framed spent
quite a few pages on specific Federalist essays
with regard to their justifications for the institutional structures I was
discussing. A central question in my
book was whether we in the 21st century agreed or disagreed with the
arguments put forth by Publius (though in that book I referred to the “real”
author of the essay in question, unlike my strategy in An Argument Open to All). In
any event, I realized two things: I
really hadn’t carefully read The
Federalist in years, probably since I was in graduate school, save for some
chestnuts like Federalist 10 and 78,
and, more importantly, that the essays as a whole were a lot more interesting
than I had thought they were. So I was
interested to see if that was in fact true of each and every one of the 85
essays. And the answer, at least to my
satisfaction, is that each one does have
something of genuine interest to a 21st century reader, independent
of the question of agreement or disagreement.
JB: You've been outspoken in calling for a new
constitutional convention, or at the very least, a series of new constitutional
amendments. But you've written a book on the most famous advertisement for our
present constitution. Do you think that The
Federalist supports your views on the need for constitutional reform?
SL: Sure! The two
most important essays in this regard are Nos. 1 and 14. The very first essay sets out what I consider
to be the most important question of our time:
Do we really believe that our fellow citizens are capable of sufficient
“reflection and choice” about essential matters of governance that we should
trust their decisions? Publius says
yes. Whether or not the actual author,
Hamilton, believed this is irrelevant to me.
And in Federalist 14, Publius emphasizes the importance of learning from
experience and rejecting “tradition” and “names” (i.e., arguments from
authority, including the authority, presumably, of “The Framers”) in favor of
thinking for ourselves. Again, if we
believe this, we should be more receptive to the idea of holding a convention
that would in fact subject the Constitution to rational scrutiny. The central problem, I am convinced, is that
most Americans—and I’m tempted to say especially those who consider themselves
“liberals,” “progressives,” of “leftists”—are scared to death of their fellow
citizens and most certainly do not believe they have the capacity to engage in
intelligent discussion of our constitutional order. That may be true, of course, but if it is,
democracy—and not merely the prospects for a new convention—is doomed.
JB: What most surprised you about The Federalist in writing your commentary?
SL: How much there is to disturb both contemporary
conservatives and liberals. The Federalist, especially No. 10,
surely the most widely-read of the 85, is an unrelenting attack on local
government and autonomy. The smaller the
governmental unit, the more likely the capure by factions. The opponents of the Constitution who accused
its supporters of advocating a “consolidated government” were, by and large,
absolutely right. The Federalist Society
should explain that the Madison they use as their logo is the Madison of 1798
and most certainly not the co-author of The
Federalist. On the other hand,
contemporary liberals concerned about what you and I have called the “national
security” and “national surveillance” states should realize that Publius was
obsessed with threats to America’s survival and, especially in Nos. 40 and 41,
but in other essays as well, basically endorsed unlimited national power to do
whatever necessary to meet such threats.
Of course, one can say, as I assume both of us would, that Republicans
greatly over-emphasize the nature of the threats posed to American security by
the international system today, but that is, in some way, to beg the
question. I.e., to what extent are we
willing to accept the proposition that in times of existential threat, the law
really should be silent?
JB: Why did you treat Publius as one person rather than
as three people? Did you come away from
your book with a different sense of any of the three authors behind the
pseudonym?
SL: I really am concerned only with whether or not these essays from long ago do (or should)
engage us today when we grapple with issues of constitutional design or the
overall project of constitutional government.
(Note, incidentally, that I don’t say “constitutional interpretation.” As a matter of fact, I think there is
astonishingly little in the 85 essays that is really useful to practicing
lawyers trying to figure out the meaning of debated clauses.) Why does it matter who wrote the essays? And, inevitably, if I had referred to the
actual authors, I would have had to address the “sincerity” question, since
it’s crystal clear that some of the specific arguments are in tension with what
Hamilton and Madison had said in Philadelphia or would go on to say when the
new government got up and running.
I suppose my principal “different sense” is that with
regard to the issues raised in my last answer, there is remarkably little
difference between Hamilton and Madison on the subordination of legal niceties
to the “exigencies” of the situation.
JB: Most law students read only a few of the essays in The Federalist. What parts of The Federalist are most relevant today
that people don't pay enough attention to? What parts do you think are least
relevant today?
SL: I have discovered, while teaching these materials at
Harvard and giving a lecture at Chicago, that very few law students have read
many of the essays. I take this as
evidence that almost no history or political science courses, even at the elite
schools from which Harvard and Chicago draw their students, bother any longer
to assign more than a very few of the essays.
If any are assigned, they are likely to be ##10, 47, 51, and 78. I think this is a shame. For starters, I would certainly assign ##1, 2,
6, 14, 15, 17, 23, 37, 40, 41, 46, 49, and almost all of the essays on
executive power, including the veto and the pardoning power. All are relevant in quite different
ways. I’ve already mentioned Federalist 1. Federalist 2, built around a preposterous
notion that there was a singular homogeneous American people in 1787, offers a
vital entry-point into the debates today about immigration, multiculturalism,
and diversity. Nos. 40-41, as already
mentioned, offer real challenges to anyone inclined to read Publius as an unabashed
admirer of “the rule of law” in times of emergency. Even some truly esoteric essays on ancient
and medieval confederations (##18-20) are altogether relevant to thinking about
the tensions facing Europe today, inasmuch as the EU is, at bottom, a mere
“confederation” and not a US-style consolidated government. Those essays are full of shrewd points on why
no “confederation,” including the US under the Articles of Confederation, can
really be effective. And I have become
especially fond, in a way, of Federalist
11 inasmuch as it explains why countries like China and Iran are altogether
rational in trying to build a strong military to defend themselves against
would-be hegemons that are certainly unfriendly to their desires to play a
stronger role in the international political-military order.
The fact is that Hamilton, Madison, and Jay were
unusually able political thinkers and masters of the rhetorical arts, and each
of their essays, if read carefully, can easily generate productive discussions
even today.
JB: Americans like to emphasize the greatness of The Federalist as a work of political
and constitutional theory, and recommend it to people in other countries. For
some time now you've been teaching courses on comparative constitutional
design. Do you think other countries have something to learn from The Federalist? If so, what parts?
SL: I think they do have something to learn, but, as I’ve
already suggested, it might not always be what the State Department intends
when it sends copies abroad. I think
that Publius writes from what we might regard as a basically Hobbesian-Machiavellian
perspective, even though, interestingly enough, neither of these great
political thinkers is ever mentioned.
But I think one message is that in the absence of a strong world
government or the kind of “natural protection” that it was thought, at the
time, was provided by the Atlantic Ocean, any country has to mobilize and even,
in some sense, adopt a militaristic culture.
One of the most fascinating essays is No. 8, in which Publius inveighs
against such cultures, which he sees as inevitable should the thirteen states
not united behind the new Constitution and instead establish two or three
separate countries that would constantly be fighting one another.
JB: Lawyers and judges love to cite The Federalist, and as Frank Cross notes, the number of citations
to The Federalist in the Supreme
Court started to explode during the Warren Court era. How important is The Federalist to contemporary
constitutional interpretation?
SL: I think it would be interesting to look at precisely which of the Federalists are cited. Anthony Kennedy loves to cite one or another
of the very few sentences that offer any real succor to federalism fans like
himself. To my knowledge, he’s never
acknowledged the arguments in Federalist 10
about states being dens of factional iniquity.
And, of course, there’s also citation by fans of executive power of the
ostensible advantages set out in Federalist
70 and elsewhere about the energetic lone executive. I’m not sure, though, whether you’re asking
an empirical or a normative question. That
is, I think that The Federalist is,
descriptively, more important than it should be to Supreme Court judges who
like to mine it for support for their own pre-ordained positions. They give wildly undue importance to the
essays, which is, I suppose, not surprising inasmuch as none of them is at all
a trained historian with an appreciation for the genuine range of views that
were contending with one another at the time.
And they pay no attention to the fact, for example, that the first
Congress rejected Publius’s assurances that Congress would play an important
role in the removal of cabinet
officials or, something that I find especially interesting, that John Marshall
in McCulloch swept aside the argument
in Federalist 33 that the inevitable
tensions that would arise vis-à-vis concurrent taxing authority would be
handled politically rather than treated as issues to be decided by judges.
So it should be clear that my hope that more attention
will be paid to The Federalist (and,
by the way, to my book) has nothing to do with their instrumental usefulness in
constitutional interpretation as that subject is defined in the contemporary
legal academy.